Skip to main content

Discretion, Judicial Independence, and Accountability

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
  • 354 Accesses

Abstract

The previous chapters have discussed organizational influences on judicial decision-making against the notion of rationality. Do organizational arrangements allow the AC to align its choices with its goals? How do bounded rationality aspects give rise to discretion? In this chapter, these organizational influences are assessed by reference to independence and accountability, two universal ideals to be pursued in judicial systems. Do these organizational impacts constitute undue influences on the independence of judiciary? Or do they promote judicial accountability to particular values?

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Former justice Sandra Day O’ Conner questions the accountability desired by the majority and puts accountability subject to the notion of independence (Connor 2008).

  2. 2.

    Principle 17 states that “[a] charge or complaint made against a judge in his/her judicial and professional capacity shall be processed expeditiously and fairly under an appropriate procedure. The judge shall have the right to a fair hearing. The examination of the matter at its initial stage shall be kept confidential, unless otherwise requested by the judge.” Principle 18 sets the grounds for removal and says that “[j]udges shall be subject to suspension or removal only for reasons of incapacity or behavior that renders them unfit to discharge their duties” (UN 1985).

  3. 3.

    Principle VI(1) spells out specific measures when judges fail to carry out responsibilities and disciplinary offenses. It states that “[w]here judges fail to carry out their duties in an efficient and proper manner or in the event of disciplinary offences, all necessary measures which do not prejudice judicial independence should be taken. Depending on the constitutional principles and the legal provisions and traditions of each state, such measures may include, for instance: a. withdrawal of cases from the judge; b. moving the judge to other judicial tasks within the court; c. economic sanctions such as a reduction in salary for a temporary period; d. suspension.”

  4. 4.

    A little different from Cappelletti’s classification, Charles Gardner Geyh provides a judicial accountability taxonomy which encompasses three categories: (1) institutional accountability (collective accountability of the judiciary as a branch of the government), (2) behavioral accountability (behavior of judges on their private capabilities), and (3) decisional accountability (discharge of professional functions) (Geyh 2006, p. 917).

  5. 5.

    Randall Peerenboom also argues for a discussion of judicial independence in authoritarian states (Peerenboom 2010). The author would like to elaborate more on this topic.

  6. 6.

    Professor He’s opinion is a little different. He insists on the concept of judicial independence, but thinks that judicial independence can be discussed in two senses: judicial power independence and adjudicative independence. He uses the term of “judicial independence” in its second sense (He 1988, p. 314).

  7. 7.

    Wang Pan and Cheng Zhengju think that Chinese adjudicative independence is a type of “technical judicial rule” which guarantees the realization of justice in judicial decision-making (Wang and Cheng 2002, pp. 54 and 58).

  8. 8.

    Zhang Min and Jiang Huiling explain that emphasis on federative power has historical reasons. At that time, a bourgeois revolution brewed across the continental Europe, and foreign affairs became an important issue for individual states (Zhang and Jiang 1998, p. 16).

  9. 9.

    The reason for this division is the historical concern over the interference of ordinary courts with the executive branch of the government. When jurisdiction conflicts arise, jurisdiction issues are decided by the Tribunal of Conflicts.

  10. 10.

    Peter H. Russell thinks highly of impartiality. He proclaims that the fundamental purpose of the principle of judicial independence is that it gives parties reason to believe that the case will be fairly handled (Russell 2001, p. 10).

  11. 11.

    He explains in this article that he defines judicial independence as independent from the executive rather than the legislature because the judiciary can never be completely independent from the legislature in consideration of the law-making functions of the legislature and provision of funding and personnel for the courts (Tiede 2006, pp. 133–134).

  12. 12.

    Fu and Randall draw a distinction between (pure) political cases and politically sensitive cases. The former directly challenge the authority of the ruling regime. The latter affect sociopolitical stability and economic growth. The latter is less directly political than the former (Fu and Peerenboom 2010, p. 96).

  13. 13.

    IPC of Puyang City Henan Province (2010). Meng Xianyan v. People’s Government of Chengguan Town Fan County.

  14. 14.

    Id. The plaintiff disagreed with this decision and appealed to the IPC of Puyang City.

  15. 15.

    Randall Peerenboom thinks that self-restraint is one strategy used by judges in certain types of cases such as corporate cases and even more clearly in high-profile cases that involve political dissidents (Peerenboom 2010, p. 15).

  16. 16.

    The duty of diligence has a close relationship with the duty of competence. An act which violates one often companies a violation of the other (American Bar Association 2003, p. 18).

  17. 17.

    Cannon 3A (1) stipulates that “[a] judge should be faithful to the law and maintain professional competence in it. A judge should be unswayed by partisan interest, public clamor, or fear of criticism.” Cannon 3B(1) specifies that “[a] judge should diligently discharge the administrative responsibilities of the office without bias or prejudice, maintain professional competence in judicial administration, and facilitate the performance of the administrative responsibilities of other judges and court officials.”

  18. 18.

    This cites some of the important legal skills, such as the analysis of precedent, the evaluation of evidence, and legal drafting. It also highlights the most fundamental legal skills, such as determining the type of legal problems that a situation may involve and the skills that necessarily transcend any particular specialized knowledge (American Bar Association 2003, p. 17).

  19. 19.

    The Court of Appeals of Maryland (2003).

  20. 20.

    No. 78,616 in the Matter of Carl S. Black (1997), http://www.kscourts.org/cases-and-opinions/opinions/supct/1997/19970711/78616.htm. Accessed 22 March 2010.

  21. 21.

    Owen makes a similar argument in the context of bureaucratization of the judiciary. He thinks that “[j]udicial independence is not threatened by bureaucratization, and, indeed, today the independence of the judiciary from the political branches might depend on its capacity to develop the organizational resources usually associated with a bureaucracy” (Fiss 1983, p. 1443).

  22. 22.

    International Bar Association Code of Minimum Standards of Judicial Independence provides personal and substantive independence for individual judges. Personal independence means “the terms and conditions of judicial service are adequately secured, so as to ensure that individual judges are not subject to executive control.” Substantive independence means “in the discharge of his judicial function, a judge is subject to nothing but the law and the commands of his conscience” (Shetreet and Deschênes 1985, p. 388).

References

  • Abraham, H. J. (1993). The judicial process: An introductory analysis of the courts of the United States, England, and France (6th ed.). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • American Bar Association. (1974). Code of judicial conduct (as amended by the New Jersey Supreme Court).

    Google Scholar 

  • American Bar Association. (1992). Statement of fundamental lawyering skills and professional values. Chicago: American Bar Association, Section of Legal Education and Admissions to the Bar.

    Google Scholar 

  • American Bar Association. (2003). Annotated model rules of professional conduct (5th ed.). Chicago: Center for Professional Responsibility, American Bar Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • Becker, T. L. (1970). Comparative judicial politics: The political functionings of courts. Chicago: Rand MaNally.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berthelemy, H. (1930). The “Conseil D’Etat” in France. Journal of Comparative Legislation and International Law, 12(1), 23–32.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burton, S. J. (1987). Particularism, discretion, and the rule of law. In A. C. Hutchinson & P. Monahan (Eds.), The rule of law: Ideal and ideology. Toronto: Carswell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, P., & Chapman, B. (1959). The constitution of the fifth republic. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cappelletti, M. (1983). “Who watches the watchmen?” A comparative study on judicial responsibility. The American Journal of Comparative Law, 31(1), 1–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ching, F. (1998). Rough justice. Far Eastern Economic Review, 161(34), 13–14.

    Google Scholar 

  • Connor, S. D. O. (2008). Judicial accountability must safeguard, not threaten, judicial independence: An introduction. Denver University Law Review, 86(1), 1–6.

    Google Scholar 

  • Council of Europe. (1994). Recommendation No.R (94) 12 of the committee of ministers to member states on the independence, Efficiency and role of judges. http://www.coe.int/t/e/legal_affairs/legal_co-operation/administrative_law_and_justice/Texts_&_Documents/Conv_Rec_Res/Recommendation(94)12.asp. Accessed 8 Mar 2010.

  • Fairlie, J. A. (1923). The separation of powers. Michigan Law Review, 21(4), 393–436.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Finer, H. (1932). The theory and practice of modern government (Vol. 1). London: Methuen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fiss, O. M. (1983). The bureaucratization of the judiciary. The Yale Law Journal, 92(8), 1442–1468.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fiss, O. M. (1993). The limits of judicial independence. University of Miami Inter-American Law Review, 25(1), 57–76.

    Google Scholar 

  • French Ministry of Foreign Affairs. (2007). Referendums in France. http://www.ambafrance-np.org/IMG/pdf/Referendums_ag.pdf. Accessed 12 Mar 2012.

  • Fu, Y., & Peerenboom, R. (2010). A new analytic framework for understanding and promoting judicial independence in China. In R. Peerenboom (Ed.), Judicial independence in China: Lessons for global rule of law promotion (pp. 95–133). Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Galligan, D. J. (1986). Discretionary powers: A legal study of official discretion. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Geyh, C. G. (2006). Rescuing judicial accountability from the realm of political rhetoric. Case Western Reserve Law Review, 56(4), 911–935.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gong, T. (2004). Dependent judiciary and unaccountable judges: Judicial corruption in contemporary China. China Review, 4(2), 33–54.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grant, R. M. (1996). Prospering in dynamically-competitive environments: Organizational capability as knowledge integration. Organization Science, 7(4), 375–387.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hack, P. (2004). Introduction: Judicial integrity. In A. Sajó (Ed.), Judicial integrity. Leiden/Boston: M. Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • He, H. (1988). Bijiao xianfaxue [Comparative constitution science]. Wu Han: Wuhan University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hohfeld, W. N. (1919). Fundamental legal conceptions as applied in judicial reasoning, and other legal essays. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Humphrey, J. P. (1946). The theory of the separation of functions. The University of Toronto Law Journal, 6(2), 331–360.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jennings, S. I. (1964). The law and the constitution (5th ed.). London: University of London Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, N. (1999). The constitution. In I. Holliday, A. Gamble, & G. Parry (Eds.), Fundamentals in British politics (pp. 45–70). Basingstoke: Macmillan; New York: St. Martin’s Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Judge, D. (2005). Political institutions in the United Kingdom. Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Judicial Group on Strengthening Judicial Integrity. (2002). The Bangalore principles of judicial conduct.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laing, J. (1982). Symposium politicization of the courts: Balancing the need for judicial independence against the need for judicial accountability (Introduction). Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy, 6(Special issue), 295–340.

    Google Scholar 

  • Larkins, C. M. (1996). Judicial independence and democratization: A theoretical and conceptual analysis. The American Journal of Comparative Law, 44(4), 605–626.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Li, J., & Dong, R. (2007). Lüshi chongdang “fubai qianke” toushi dangqian sifa fubai’an santedian [Lawyers as corruption broker reflect three characteristics of present judicial corruption cases]. http://news.xinhuanet.com/legal/2007–06/07/content_6210060.htm. Accessed 1 Apr 2010.

  • Locke, J. (1988). Two treatises of government (Student Ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Montesquieu, B. D. (1966). The spirit of the laws (T. Nugent, Trans.). New York/London: Hafner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nemetz, N. T. (1977). Judicial administration and an independent judiciary. South African Law Journal, 94, 80–86.

    Google Scholar 

  • NPC. (1982). Xianfa [Constitution].

    Google Scholar 

  • NPCSC. (1979). Renmin fayuan zuzhi fa [Organic law of the people’s courts].

    Google Scholar 

  • Oregon Supreme Court. (1996). Oregon code of judicial conduct.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oshana, M. (2006). Personal autonomy in society. Aldershot/Burlington: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paine, T. (1984). Rights of man. Harmondsworth/New York: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peerenboom, R. (2010). Introduction. In R. Peerenboom (Ed.), Judicial independence in China: Lessons for global rule of law promotion (pp. 1–22). New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Penrose, E. T. (1995). The theory of the growth of the firm (3rd ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pimentel, D. (2009). Reframing the independence v. Accountability debate: Defining judicial structure in light of judges’ courage and integrity. Cleveland State Law Review, 57(1), 1–33.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz, J. (1998). Voluntary obligation and normative powers. In S. L. Paulson & B. L. Paulson (Eds.), Normativity and norms (pp. 451–470). Oxford/New York: Clarendon Press/Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Renstrom, P. G. (1991). The American law dictionary. Santa Barbara: ABC-Clio.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenn, K. S. (1987). The protection of judicial independence in Latin America. Inter-American Law Review, 19(1), 1–35.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, P. H. (2001). Toward a general theory of judicial independence. In P. H. Russell & D. M. O’Brien (Eds.), Judicial independence in the age of democracy: Critical perspectives from around the world (pp. 1–24). Charlottesville: University Press of Virginia.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shetreet, S. (1984). Judicial independence and accountability in Israel. International and Comparative Law Quarterly, 33(4), 979–1012.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shetreet, S. (1985). Judicial independence: New conceptual dimensions and contemporary challenges. In S. Shetreet & J. Deschenes (Eds.), Judicial independence: The contemporary debate. Dordrecht: Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shetreet, S., & Deschenes, J. (Eds.). (1985). International Bar Association code of minimum standards of judicial independence. In judicial independence: The contemporary debate. Dordrecht: Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stephen, S. N. (1985). Judicial independence: A fragile bastion. In S. Shetreet & J. Deschenes (Eds.), Judicial independence: The contemporary debate. Dordrecht: Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • The Court of Appeals of Maryland. (2003). Attorney Grievance Comm’n v. Davis. http://caselaw.lp.findlaw.com/data2/marylandstatecases/coa/2003/43a02ag.pdf. Accessed 21 Mar 2010.

  • Tian, Y. (2009). Qianlun faguan fubai de fangzhi – you Zhou Wenxuan’an yinfa de sikao [Studies on judicial corruption prevention: Reflections on the Zhou Wenxuan case]. Xue lilun [Theory Research], 17, 131–132.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tiede, L. B. (2006). Judicial independence: Often cited, rarely understood. Journal of Contemporary Legal Issues, 15(1), 129–162.

    Google Scholar 

  • UN. (1985). Basic principles on the independence of the judiciary.

    Google Scholar 

  • US. (1787). The constitution of the United States of America.

    Google Scholar 

  • Verner, J. G. (1984). The independence of supreme courts in Latin America: A review of the literature. Journal of Latin American Studies, 16(2), 463–506.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wang, P., & Cheng, Z. (2002). Shenpan duli yu sifa gongzheng [Adjudicative independence and judicial justice]. Beijing: Chinese People’s Public Security University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wanlass, L. C. (1959). Gettell’s history of political thought (2nd ed.). London: Allen & Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilkinson, J. H., III. (1989). The role of reason in the rule of law. The University of Chicago Law Review, 56(2), 779–809.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zhang, M., & Jiang, H. (1998). Fayuan duli shenpan wenti yanjiu [Study on the independent adjudication of the court]. Beijing: People’s Court Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Li, L. (2014). Discretion, Judicial Independence, and Accountability. In: Judicial Discretion within Adjudicative Committee Proceedings in China. Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-642-54041-7_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics