Skip to main content

Metaphor and Model-Based Reasoning in Maxwell’s Mathematical Physics

  • Conference paper
  • First Online:
Model-Based Reasoning in Science and Technology

Part of the book series: Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics ((SAPERE,volume 8))

Abstract

The role of model-based reasoning in experimental and theoretical scientific thinking has been extensively studied. However, little work has been done on the role of mathematical representations in such thinking. I will describe how the nature of mathematical expressions in physics can be analyzed using an extension of the metaphoric analysis of mathematics. Lakoff and Núñez [29] argued that embodied metaphors underlie basic mathematical ideas (e.g., the concept of “number” is based on the embodied operations of “collecting objects”), with more complex expressions developed via conceptual blends from simpler expressions (e.g., “addition” as “combining collections”). In physics, however, the need to represent physical processes and observed entities (including measurements) places different demands on the blending processes. In model-based reasoning, conceptual blends must often be based on immediately available embodiments as well as highly developed mathematical expressions that draw upon long term working memory. Thus, Faraday’s representations of magnetic fields as “lines of force” were modeled by Maxwell as vectors. In the paper, I compare Faraday’s experimental investigation of the magnetic field within a magnet to Maxwell’s mathematical treatment of the same problem. Both can be understood by unpacking the metaphoric underpinnings as physical representations. The implications for analogical and model-based reasoning accounts of scientific thinking are discussed.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 169.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    The embodiment of metaphor will also be assumed here, and is important to the notion of model based reasoning as a species of abduction (e.g., [33]). For further discussion of these issues, see Cat [3], Gooding [21], Nersessian [39], and Tweney [51]. Simpson [42, 41], while emphasizing the rhetoric of Maxwell's Treatise, is advancing a similar argument.

  2. 2.

    Note also that my approach differs from accounts that regard metaphor as a somewhat loose use of similarity, while analogy has been regarded as founded on more severe constraints. See Gentner and Jerzioski [17], which adopts such a view. I am using the two terms in unconventional fashion, with metaphor referring to implicit comparisons and analogy to those drawn explicitly.

  3. 3.

    A good brief introduction to Faraday's work is James [25]. For Maxwell, a good beginning is Everitt [8]. Both works acknowledge the nuances!

  4. 4.

    Maxwell's famous derivation, suggesting that light was an electromagnetic manifestation, appeared initially in the second paper, was re-expressed in the third paper, and finalized at the end of the Treatise.

  5. 5.

    Thomson [47] had considered a problem similar to Maxwell's, in determining the force on a unit pole placed within a small cavity in a magnet. However he did not resolve the directional paradox between the directions of what were later called B and H by Maxwell. Smith and Wise ([44], pp. 279–281) describe Thomson's approach and indicate that he did not fully publish his results.

  6. 6.

    It is interesting to note the similarity of this maneuver to that used by Lakatos in Proofs and refutations, which used a similar ploy to discuss the nature of discovery in mathematical proof [29].

  7. 7.

    Indeed, the terms, analogy and metaphor, have had a flexible boundary in much of the writing about their use in science. Thus, for example, much of what Bradie [1] has written about metaphor applies equally to analogy.

References

  1. Bradie, M.: Models and metaphors in science: the metaphorical turn. Protosociology 12, 305–318 (1998)

    Google Scholar 

  2. Cat, J.: On understanding: Maxwell on the methods of illustration and scientific metaphor. Stud. Hist. Philos. Mod. Phys. 32, 395–441 (2001)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  3. Cat, J.: Into the ‘regions of physical and metaphysical chaos’: Maxwell’s scientific metaphysics and natural philosophy of action (agency, determinacy and necessity from theology, moral philosophy and history to mathematics, theory and experiment). Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. 43, 91–104 (2011)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. Chi, M.T.H., Feltovich, P.J., Glaser, R.: Categorization and representation of physics problems by experts and novices. Cogn. Sci. 5, 121–152 (1981)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. Clement, J.: Creative Model Construction in Scientists and Students: Imagery, Analogy, and Mental Simulation. Springer, Dordrecht (2008)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  6. Crowe, M.J.: A History of Vector Analysis. University of Notre Dame Press, South Bend (1967)

    Google Scholar 

  7. Ericsson, K.A., Kintsch, W.: Long-term working memory. Psychol. Rev. 102, 211–245 (1995)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. Everitt, C.W.F.: James Clerk Maxwell: Physicist and Natural Philosopher. Charles Scribner’s Sons, New York (1975)

    Google Scholar 

  9. Faraday, M.: Experimental Researches in Electricity, Nineteenth Series. On the Magnetization of Light and the Illumination of Magnetic Lines of Force. Taylor & Francis, London (1846) (Reprinted in M. Faraday (ed.) (1855) Experimental researches in electricity vol. 3, pp. 1–26)

    Google Scholar 

  10. Faraday, M.: Experimental Researches in Electricity, Twenty-Eighth series. On Lines of Magnetic Force: Their Definite Character; and Their Distribution Within a Magnet and Through Space. Taylor & Francis, London (1851) (Reprinted in M. Faraday (ed.) (1855) Experimental researches in electricity, vol. 3, pp. 328–370)

    Google Scholar 

  11. Faraday, M.: On the Physical Character of the Lines of Magnetic Force. Taylor & Francis, London (1852) (Reprinted in M. Faraday (ed.) (1855) Experimental researches in electricity, vol. 3, pp. 407–437)

    Google Scholar 

  12. Feist, G.J., Gorman, M.E. (eds.): Handbook of the Psychology of Science. Springer, New York (2013)

    Google Scholar 

  13. Fisher, H.: Maxwell’s Treatise on Electricity and Magnetism: The Central Argument. Green Lion Press, Santa Fe (in press)

    Google Scholar 

  14. Forbus, K.: Reasoning about space and motion. In: Gentner, D., Stevens, A. (eds.) Mental Models, pp. 53–74. Lawrence Erlbaum, Hillsdale (1983)

    Google Scholar 

  15. Garber, E.: The Language of Physics: The Calculus and the Development of Theoretical Physics in Europe, 1750–1914. Birkhäuser, Boston (1999)

    Google Scholar 

  16. Gentner, D., Bowdle, B.: Metaphor as structure-mapping. In: Gibbs Jr, R.W. (ed.) The Cambridge Handbook of Metaphor and Thought, pp. 109–128. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2008)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  17. Gentner, D., Jeziorski, : The shift from metaphor to analogy in Western science. In: Ortony, A. (ed.) Metaphor and Thought, 2nd edn, pp. 447–480. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1993)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  18. Gibbs Jr, R.W.: Why many concepts are metaphorical. Cognition 61, 309–319 (1996)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  19. Gibbs Jr, R.W., Perlman, M.: Language understanding is grounded in experiential simulations: a response to Weiskopf. Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. 41, 305–308 (2010)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  20. Gooding, D.C.: Final steps to the field theory: Faraday’s study of magnetic phenomena. Hist. Stud. Phys. Sci. 11, 231–275 (1981)

    Google Scholar 

  21. Gooding, D.: Experiment and the Making of Meaning: Human Agency in Scientific Observation and Experiment. Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht (1990)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  22. Grattan-Guinness, I.: The Fontana History of the Mathematical Sciences: The Rainbow of Mathematics. Fontana Press, London (1997)

    Google Scholar 

  23. Harman, P.M.: The Natural Philosophy of James Clerk Maxwell. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1998)

    Google Scholar 

  24. Hunt, B.R.: The Maxwellians. Cornell University Press, Ithaca (2005)

    Google Scholar 

  25. James, F.A.J.L.: Michael Faraday: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2010)

    Google Scholar 

  26. Johnson-Laird, P.N.: Mental models in cognitive science. Cognitive Science 4, 71–115 (1980)

    Google Scholar 

  27. Kurz-Milcke, E.: The authority of representations. In: Kurz-Milcke, E., Gigerenzer, G. (eds.) Experts in Science and Society, pp. 281–302. Kluwer Academic/Plenum, New York (2004)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  28. Lagrange, J.L.: Analytical Mechanics (trans. ed. by A.C. Boissonnade, and V.N. Vagliente). Kluwer Academic Publishers, Boston (1788/1997)

    Google Scholar 

  29. Lakatos, I.: Proofs and Refutations. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1963–1964/1976). (Originally published in British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 14)

    Google Scholar 

  30. Lakoff, G., Johnson, M.: Philosophy in the Flesh: The Embodied Mind and its Challenge to Modern Thought. Basic Books, New York (1999)

    Google Scholar 

  31. Lakoff, G., Núñez, R.E.: Where Mathematics Comes From: How the Embodied Mind Brings Mathematics into Being. Basic Books, New York (2000)

    Google Scholar 

  32. Larkin, J.H., McDermott, J., Simon, D.P., Simon, H.A.: Models of competence in solving physics problems. Cogn. Sci. 4, 317–345 (1980)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  33. Magnani, L.: Abduction, Reason, and Science: Processes of Discovery and Explanation. Kluwer Academic/Plenum Publishers, New York (2001)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  34. Maxwell, J.C. (undated, c. 1870/1882). To the chief musician upon Nabla. In: Campbell, L., Garnett, W. (eds.) (1882). The Life of James Clerk Maxwell, pp. 634–636. Macmillan, London

    Google Scholar 

  35. Maxwell, J.C.: A treatise on Electricity and Magnetism (2 volumes). Clarendon Press, Oxford. (1873/1891) (Third edition, revised by J.J. Thompson)

    Google Scholar 

  36. Murphy, G.L.: On metaphoric representation. Cognition 60, 173–204 (1996)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  37. Murphy, G.L.: Reasons to doubt the present evidence for metaphoric representation. Cognition 62, 99–108 (1997)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  38. Nersessian, N.: Faraday to Einstein: Constructing Meaning in Scientific Theories. Nijhoff, Dordrecht (1984)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  39. Nersessian, N.J.: Creating Scientific Concepts. MIT Press, Cambridge (2008)

    Google Scholar 

  40. Núñez, R.E.: Creating mathematical infinites: metaphor, blending, and the beauty of transfinite cardinals. J. Pragmat. 37, 1717–1741 (2005)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  41. Siegel, D.M.: Innovation in Maxwell’s Electromagnetic Theory: Molecular Vortices, Displacement Current, and Light. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1991)

    Google Scholar 

  42. Simpson, T.K.: Figures of Thought: A Literary Appreciation of Maxwell’s Treatise on Electricity and Magnetism. Green Lion Press, Santa Fe (2005)

    Google Scholar 

  43. Simpson, T.K.: Maxwell’s Mathematical Rhetoric: Rethinking the Treatise on Electricity and Magnetism. Green Lion Press, Santa Fe (2010)

    Google Scholar 

  44. Smith, C., Wise, M.N.: Energy & empire: A biographical study of Lord Kelvin. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1989)

    Google Scholar 

  45. Thomson, W. (Lord Kelvin): On the uniform motion of heat in homogeneous solid bodies, and its connexion with the mathematical theory of electricity. In: Thomson, W. (ed.) Reprint of Papers on Electrostatics and Magnetism, pp. 1–14. Macmillan & Co, London. (1842/1872) (Originally published 1842)

    Google Scholar 

  46. Thomson, W. (Lord Kelvin): On the mathematical theory of electricity in equilibrium I. On the elementary laws of statical electricity. In: Thomson, W. (ed.) Reprint of Papers on Electrostatics and Magnetism, pp. 15–37. Macmillan & Co, London. (1845/1872) (Originally published 1845)

    Google Scholar 

  47. Thomson, W. (Lord Kelvin): A mathematical theory of magnetism. In: Thomson, W. (ed.) Reprint of Papers on Electrostatics and Magnetism, pp. 340–425. Macmillan & Co., London (1849/1872) (Originally published 1849)

    Google Scholar 

  48. Turner, M.: Cognitive Dimensions of Social Science. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2001)

    Google Scholar 

  49. Tweney, R.D.: Inventing the field: Michael Faraday and the creative “engineering” of electromagnetic field theory. In: Weber, R.J., Perkins, D.N. (eds.) Inventive Minds: Creativity in Technology, pp. 31–47. Oxford University Press, Oxford (1992)

    Google Scholar 

  50. Tweney, R.D.: Representing the electromagnetic field: how Maxwell’s mathematics empowered Faraday’s field theory. Sci. Educ. 20(7–8), 687–700 (2011)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  51. Tweney, R.D.: On the unreasonable reasonableness of mathematical physics: a cognitive view. In: Proctor, R.W., Capaldi, E.J. (eds.) Psychology of Science: Implicit and Explicit Processes, pp. 406–435. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2012)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  52. Warwick, A.: Masters of Theory: Cambridge and the Rise of Mathematical Physics. University of Chicago Press, Chicago (2003)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  53. Weiskopf, D.A.: Embodied cognition and linguistic comprehension. Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. 41, 294–304 (2010)

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Thanks are due especially to Howard Fisher, who has saved me from many errors and is not responsible for remaining ones! I have benefitted greatly from discussions of Maxwell with John Clement, Howard Fisher, Frank James, Nancy Nersessian, and Thomas Simpson. The paper’s ultimate origin stems from discussions with the late David Gooding and with Elke Kurz-Milcke. The proximate origin is a paper given at MBR012 in Sestri Levante, Italy, in June, 2012; I am grateful for the questions and comments of the other participants and to Lorenzo Magnani for his support. Matt Lira and Frank James provided helpful comments on an early draft, for which I am grateful.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ryan D. Tweney .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg

About this paper

Cite this paper

Tweney, R.D. (2014). Metaphor and Model-Based Reasoning in Maxwell’s Mathematical Physics. In: Magnani, L. (eds) Model-Based Reasoning in Science and Technology. Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics, vol 8. Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-642-37428-9_21

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics