Advertisement

Quantum Phenomenology and Dynamic Co-emergence

  • Christian Flender
Conference paper
Part of the Lecture Notes in Computer Science book series (LNCS, volume 7052)

Abstract

Conceptual similarities between phenomenological descriptions of conscious experience and non-local effects as found in quantum mechanics are difficult to dismiss. Our engaged being-in-the-world, for instance when being immersed in reading, writing, or speaking, lacks a clear self-other distinction and mind-body separation as much as combined quantum systems lack separability of entangled states. Our sense of affordances or possibilities, for instance when choosing among several opportunities for action, is strongly reminiscent of superpositions or potentiality states as opposed to the factual reality of eigenstates. Since we can hardly give causally necessary and sufficient conditions for our actions causality breaks as much for intentional action as for state reduction, or wave function collapse, in the quantum world. Intentional action is always already entangled and therefore emerges from embodied and embedded comportment as much as intentionality modulates or submerges our involvement in the world. It is argued that understanding skilful coping as a mode of being-in-the-world is best conceptualized as a dynamically co-emerging whole prior to any mind-body and self-other distinction. Some elements of work practices in air traffic control are discussed as an illustrative application.

Keywords

Skilful Coping Work Practice Intentional Action Conscious Experience Paper Strip 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. 1.
    Dreyfus, H.: Being-in-the-world: A commentary on Heidegger’s Being and Time, Division I. MIT Press, Cambridge (1991)Google Scholar
  2. 2.
    Heidegger, M.: Being and Time. Blackwell Publishing, Malden (1962)Google Scholar
  3. 3.
    Dennett, D.: Darwin’s dangerous idea: Evolution and the meanings of life. Simon & Schuster, New York (1995)Google Scholar
  4. 4.
    Searle, J.: Mind: A Brief Introduction. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2004)Google Scholar
  5. 5.
    Chalmers, D.: Facing up to the problem of consciousness. In: Explaining Consciousness: The Hard Problem, pp. 9–32. MIT Press, Cambridge (1997)Google Scholar
  6. 6.
    Skinner, B., Frederic, B.: Science and Human Behavior. Free Press, New York (1965)Google Scholar
  7. 7.
    Kosslyn, S.: Image and Brain. MIT Press, Cambridge (1994)Google Scholar
  8. 8.
    Kim, J.: Emergence: Core ideas and issues. Synthese 151, 547–559 (2006)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. 9.
    Hanna, R., Thompson, E.: The mind-body-body problem. Theoria et Historia Scientiarum: International Journal for Interdisciplinary Studies 7, 24–44 (2003)Google Scholar
  10. 10.
    Atmanspacher, H.: Contextual emergence from physics to cognitive neuroscience. Journal of Consciousness Studies 14, 18 (2007)Google Scholar
  11. 11.
    Bitbol, M.: Ontology, matter and emergence. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 6, 293–307 (2007)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. 12.
    Thompson, E.: Mind in Life - Biology, Phenomenology and the Sciences of Mind. Harvard University Press, Cambridge (2007)Google Scholar
  13. 13.
    Filk, T., von Müller, A.: Quantum Physics and Consciousness: The Quest for a Common Conceptual Foundation. Mind and Matter 7(1), 59–79 (2009)Google Scholar
  14. 14.
    Mackay, W.: Is Paper Safer? The Role of Paper Flight Strips in Air Traffic Control. ACM Transactions on Human-Computer Interaction 6(4), 311–340 (1999)CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg 2011

Authors and Affiliations

  • Christian Flender
    • 1
  1. 1.University of FreiburgGermany

Personalised recommendations