Advertisement

Lexicographic Path Induction

  • Jeffrey Sarnat
  • Carsten Schürmann
Part of the Lecture Notes in Computer Science book series (LNCS, volume 5608)

Abstract

Programming languages theory is full of problems that reduce to proving the consistency of a logic, such as the normalization of typed lambda-calculi, the decidability of equality in type theory, equivalence testing of traces in security, etc. Although the principle of transfinite induction is routinely employed by logicians in proving such theorems, it is rarely used by programming languages researchers, who often prefer alternatives such as proofs by logical relations and model theoretic constructions. In this paper we harness the well-foundedness of the lexicographic path ordering to derive an induction principle that combines the comfort of structural induction with the expressive strength of transfinite induction. Using lexicographic path induction, we give a consistency proof of Martin-Löf’s intuitionistic theory of inductive definitions. The consistency of Heyting arithmetic follows directly, and weak normalization for Gödel’s T follows indirectly; both have been formalized in a prototypical extension of Twelf.

Keywords

Atomic Formula Predicate Symbol Sequent Calculus Proof Tree Proof Rule 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. [Bit99]
    Tahhan Bittar, E.: Strong normalization proofs for cut-elimination in Gentzen’s sequent calculi. In: Proceedings of the Symposium: Algebra and Computer Science. Helena Rasiowa in memoriam, vol. 46, pp. 179–225. Banach Center Publications (1999)Google Scholar
  2. [Bro06]
    Brotherston, J.: Sequent Calculus Proof Systems for Inductive Definitions. PhD thesis, University of Edinburgh (November 2006)Google Scholar
  3. [Buc95]
    Buchholz, W.: Proof-theoretic analysis of termination proofs. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic 75(1-2), 57–65 (1995)MathSciNetCrossRefzbMATHGoogle Scholar
  4. [DO88]
    Dershowitz, N., Okada, M.: Proof-theoretic techniques for term rewriting theory. In: LICS, pp. 104–111. IEEE Computer Society Press, Los Alamitos (1988)Google Scholar
  5. [DP98]
    Dyckhoff, R., Pinto, L.: Cut-elimination and a permutation-free sequent calculus for intuitionistic logic. Studia Logica 60(1), 107–118 (1998)MathSciNetCrossRefzbMATHGoogle Scholar
  6. [Dyb91]
    Dybjer, P.: Inductive sets and families in Martin-Löf’s type theory and their set-theoretic semantics. In: Logical Frameworks, pp. 280–306. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1991)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. [Gen69]
    Gentzen, G.: New version of the consistency proof for elementary number theory. In: Szabo, M.E. (ed.) The Collected Papers of Gerhard Gentzen, pp. 252–286. North-Holland Publishing Co., Amsterdam (1969)Google Scholar
  8. [GMN08]
    Gacek, A., Miller, D., Nadathur, G.: Combining generic judgments with recursive definitions. In: Pfenning, F. (ed.) Proceedings of LICS 2008, pp. 33–44. IEEE Computer Society, Los Alamitos (2008)Google Scholar
  9. [How70]
    Howard, W.A.: Assignment of ordinals to terms for primitive recursive functions of finite type. In: Kino, A., Myhill, J., Vesley, R.E. (eds.) Intuitionism and Proof Theory, pp. 443–458. North-Holland, Amsterdam (1970)Google Scholar
  10. [KL80]
    Kamin, S., Levy, J.-J.: Attemps for generalising the recursive path orderings. Unpublished lecture notes (1980)Google Scholar
  11. [ML71]
    Martin-Löf, P.: Hauptsatz for the intuitionistic theory of iterated inductive definitions. In: Fenstad, J.E. (ed.) Proceedings of the Second Scandinavian Logic Symposium. North-Holland, Amsterdam (1971)Google Scholar
  12. [MM00]
    McDowell, R., Miller, D.: Cut-elimination for a logic with definitions and induction. Theoretical Computer Science 232(1-2), 91–119 (2000)MathSciNetCrossRefzbMATHGoogle Scholar
  13. [Mos04]
    Georg Moser, I.L.: Why ordinals are good for you. In: ESSLLI 2003 - Course Material II. Collegium Logicum, vol. 6, pp. 1–65. The Kurt Gödel Society (2004)Google Scholar
  14. [MT03]
    Momigliano, A., Tiu, A.: Induction and co-induction in sequent calculus. In: Berardi, S., Coppo, M., Damiani, F. (eds.) TYPES 2003. LNCS, vol. 3085, pp. 293–308. Springer, Heidelberg (2004)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. [Pfe95]
    Pfenning, F.: Structural cut elimination. In: Kozen, D. (ed.) Proceedings of the Tenth Annual Symposium on Logic in Computer Science, San Diego, California, pp. 156–166. IEEE Computer Society Press, Los Alamitos (1995)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. [PM93]
    Paulin-Mohring, C.: Inductive Definitions in the System Coq - Rules and Properties. In: Bezem, M., Groote, J.F. (eds.) TLCA 1993. LNCS, vol. 664. Springer, Heidelberg (1993); LIP research report 92-49CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. [Sch77]
    Schütte, K.: Proof Theory. Springer, Heidelberg (1977)CrossRefzbMATHGoogle Scholar
  18. [SS08]
    Schürmann, C., Sarnat, J.: Structural logical relations. In: Pfenning, F. (ed.) Proceedings of LICS 2008, pp. 69–80. IEEE Computer Society Press, Los Alamitos (2008)Google Scholar
  19. [TS00]
    Troelstra, A.S., Schwichtenberg, H.: Basic Proof Theory, 2nd edn. Cambridge Tracts in Theoretical Computer Science, vol. 43. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2000)CrossRefzbMATHGoogle Scholar
  20. [Urb01]
    Urban, C.: Strong normalisation for a Gentzen-like cut-elimination procedure. In: Proceedings of the 5th International Conference on Typed Lambda Calculi and Applications, Krakow, Poland, May 2001, pp. 415–442 (2001)Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg 2009

Authors and Affiliations

  • Jeffrey Sarnat
    • 1
  • Carsten Schürmann
    • 2
  1. 1.Yale UniversityUSA
  2. 2.IT University of CopenhagenDenmark

Personalised recommendations