Skip to main content

Inference to the Best Explanation

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Truth-Seeking by Abduction

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 400))

  • 484 Accesses

Abstract

While Chap. 6 discussed the role of abduction in the confirmation of hypotheses by their success in explanation and prediction, in this chapter we turn to the notion acceptance which is a stronger form of justification than confirmation. Section 7.1 gives a survey of inductive acceptance rules, and following Gilbert Harman formulates inference to the best explanation (IBE) as a rule of acceptance: a hypothesis H may be inferred from evidence E when H is a better explanation of E than any other rival hypothesis. The notion of “best explanation” is explicated by measures of explanatory power, with a comparison to Lipton’s distinction between “lovely” and “likely” explanations. In the special case with only one available explanation, IBE reduces to inference to the only explanation. Section 7.2 deals with the question of justifying IBE by giving replies to Bas van Fraassen’s “bad lot” and “incoherence” arguments. It is concluded that under certain conditions an explanatory hypothesis may be so successful that its tentative acceptance as true is warranted.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 89.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Convergence theorems of de Finetti and Savage show that under some conditions researchers, who update their personal degrees of beliefs by the same evidence , are eventually led from different prior probabilities to the same posterior probabilities. See Howson and Urbach (1989) and Earman (1992) . Objective Bayesians suggest that there are unique ways of fixing the prior probabilities.

  2. 2.

    Similarly, low probability is not a sufficient condition for rejecting a hypothesis.

  3. 3.

    For example, in a language with two monadic predicates F and G, the Q-predicates are Q1x = Fx & Gx, Q2x = Fx & ¬Gx, Q3x = ¬Fx & Gx and Q4x = ¬Fx & ¬Gx. The generalization g = (∀x)(Fx → Gx) states that the cell Q2 is empty, so that it can be expressed as a disjunction of seven constituents which leave Q2 empty. (The constituent which leaves all four Q-predicates empty is excluded, since the universe cannot be empty.) If the probabilities of finding an individual b in the four Q-predicates are equal, then we have 1/3 = P(Fb/g) < P(Fb/Gb & g) = ½, which shows that Gb confirms Fb relative to g (cf. (6.5)). But to formalize singular abduction (1.3), so that Fb is acceptable on Gb and g, we need to assume that the probabilities the Q-predicates are non-symmetric, i.e. P(Q1b) is much larger than P(Q3b).

  4. 4.

    This means that in inferential problems, which are defined relative to an ultimate partition , there is no problem with the “bad lot” (cf. van Fraassen, 1989) . See below Section 7.2.

  5. 5.

    In Risto Hilpinen’s (1968) modified version, the expected utility is P(H/E) – qP(H), where 0 < q ≤ 1 is an “index of boldness” in Levi’s sense. Thus, for (3), this index of boldness is maximal. However, even the boldest application of Levi’s rule is cautious in the sense that it always prefers truth to falsity. In Chap. 8, we shall introduce measures of truthlikeness which admit that some false statements may be so close to the truth that they are cognitively better than weak uninformative truths like tautologies.

  6. 6.

    Levi (1979) restricts the task of abduction to the formulation of potential hypotheses, without reference to explanation, but here we are interested in the role of abduction in the selection of the best hypothesis.

  7. 7.

    For discussion of this thesis, see Sect. 1.4.

  8. 8.

    See also formulations of abduction as a rule of inference in Chap. 3.

  9. 9.

    Bird (2010) , who calls such deduction “Holmesian inference”, argues that Lipton’s (1991) historical example of Ignaz Semmelweis’s study of childbed fever (see Hempel, 1966) is an eliminative abduction in this strong sense. But one may doubt that the list of potential explanations that Semmelweis considered was exhaustive.

  10. 10.

    If the coroner is asked to identify the cause of death, a disjunction of even two alternative causes may be too weak.

  11. 11.

    It is questionable whether IBE can be saved from these troubles by joining it with simplicity considerations, such as “consilience ” in Thagard (1978) and “explanatory unification ” in Friedman (1974) or with additional penalties for “conceptual problems” (cf. problem-solving ability in Laudan, 1977) .

  12. 12.

    For an attempt to find objective prior probabilities for IBE, see Weisberg (2009) . In Carnap’s and Hintikka’s systems of inductive logic, there are canonical ways of giving prior distributions and likelihoods , but they are open up to the choice of one or two parameters.

  13. 13.

    An important contemporary example of the power of explanatory considerations is the postulate of dark matter. The majority of physicist accept the existence of dark matter as an abductive solution to the problem of “missing masses”, since it explains anomalous observations about galaxies, even though dark matter by definition is invisible (does not interact with electromagnetic radiation), and experimental attempts to verify or test its existence have failed. Therefore, some philosophers have claimed that it is an untestable ad hoc hypothesis (see Merritt, 2017). See also Sect. 8.5.

  14. 14.

    For critical evaluation of van Fraassen’s arguments, see Kvanvig (1994) , Psillos (1996, 1999) , Douven (1999) , Okasha (2000) , Niiniluoto (2004), and Henderson (2014). For defense, see Ladyman et al. (1997) .

  15. 15.

    Another case which guarantees that P(H/E) is close to one is that H has a unique novel deductive prediction E which no rival of H is able to predict (see Leplin 2004) .

Bibliography

  • Barnes, E. (1995). Inference to the loveliest explanation. Synthese, 103, 251–278.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bird, A. (2010). Eliminative abduction – Examples from medicine. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 4, 345–352.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boole, G. (1958). The laws of thought. New York: Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1962). Logical foundations of probability (2nd ed.). Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cleland, C. (2002). Methodological and epistemic differences between historical science and experimental science. Philosophy of Science, 69, 474–496.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Day, T., & Kincaid, H. (1994). Putting inference to the best explanation in its place. Synthese, 98, 271–295.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Douven, I. (1999). Inference to the best explanation made coherent. Philosophy of Science (Proceedings), 66, S424–S435.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Douven, I. (2011). Abduction. In E. Zalta (Ed.), Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Stanford: Stanford University. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2011/entries/abduction/

  • Earman, J. (1992). Bayes or bust? A critical examination of Bayesian confirmation theory. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, A. (1986). Unnatural attitudes: Realist and instrumentalist attachments to science. Mind, 95, 149–179.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. (1974). Explanation and scientific understanding. The Journal of Philosophy, 71, 1–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (1965). Inference to the best explanation. The Philosophical Review, 74, 88–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. G. (1965). Aspects of scientific explanation. New York: The Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. G. (1966). Philosophy of natural science. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Henderson, L. (2014). Bayesianism and Inference to the Best Explanation. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 65, 687-715.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hilpinen, R. (1968). Rules of acceptance and inductive logic (Acta Philosophica Fennica 22). Amsterdam: North-Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, J. (1968). The varieties of information and scientific explanation. In B. van Rootselaar & J. F. Staal (Eds.), Logic, methodology, and philosophy of science III (pp. 151–171). Amsterdam: North-Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, J., & Suppes, P. (Eds.). (1966). Aspects of inductive logic. Amsterdam: North-Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Howson, C., & Urbach, P. (1989). Scientific reasoning: The Bayesian approach. La Salle, IL: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Josephson, J., & Josephson, S. (Eds.). (1994). Abductive inference. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kvanvig, J. L. (1994). A critique of van Fraassens voluntaristic epistemology. Synthese, 98, 325–348.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, J., Douven, I., Horsten, L., & van Fraassen, B. C. (1997). A defence of van Fraassen’s critique of abductive reasoning: Reply to Psillos. The Philosophical Quarterly, 47, 305–321.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. (1977). Progress and its problems. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. (1984). Science and values: The aims of science and their role in scientific debate. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leplin, J. (2004). A theory’s predictive success can warrant belief in the unobservable entities it postulates. In C. Hitchcock (Ed.), Contemporary debates in philosophy of science (pp. 117–132). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levi, I. (1967). Gambling with truth. New York: Alfred A. Knopf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levi, I. (1979). Abduction and demands of information. In I. Niiniluoto & R. Tuomela (Eds.), The logic and epistemology of scientific change (Acta Philosophica Fennica 30, pp. 405–429). Amsterdam: North-Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lipton, P. (2001b). Is explanation a guide to inference? A reply to Wesley C. Salmon. In Hon & Rakover (Eds.), pp. 93–120.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lipton, P. (1991). Inference to the best explanation. London: Routledge (Second edition in 2004).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Merritt, D. (2017). Cosmology and convention. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 57, 41-52.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nelson, D. E. (1996). Confirmation, explanation, and logical strength. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 47, 399–413.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Niiniluoto, I. (1987). Truthlikeness. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Niiniluoto, I. (1990a). Measuring the success of science. In A. Fine, M. Forbes, & L. Wessels (Eds.), PSA 1990 (Vol. 1, pp. 435–445). East Lansing: Philosophy of Science Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • Niiniluoto, I. (1994). Descriptive and inductive simplicity. In W. Salmon & G. Wolters (Eds.), Logic, language, and the structure of scientific theories (pp. 147–170). Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Niiniluoto, I. (1999a). Critical scientific realism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Niiniluoto, I. (1999b). Defending abduction. Philosophy of Science (Proceedings), 66, S436–S451.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Niiniluoto, I. (2004). Truth-seeking by abduction. In F. Stadler (Ed.), Induction and deduction in the sciences (pp. 57–82). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Niiniluoto, I. (2011c). The development of the Hintikka Program. In D. Gabbay, S. Hartmann, & J. Woods (Eds.), Handbook of the History of Logic, vol. 10: Inductive Logic (pp. 311–356). Amsterdam: North-Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Niiniluoto, I. (2017). Optimistic realism about scientific progress. Synthese, 194, 3291–3309.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Okasha, S. (2000). Van Fraassen’s critique of inference to the best explanation. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 31, 691–710.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R. (1972). Objective knowledge: An evolutionary approach. Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Revised edition 1979).

    Google Scholar 

  • Psillos, S. (1996). On van Fraassen’s critique of abductive reasoning. The Philosophical Quarterly, 46, 31–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Psillos, S. (1999). Scientific realism: How science tracks truth. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Psillos, S. (2002). Simply the best: A case for abduction. In A. Kakas & F. Sadri (Eds.), Computational logic (pp. 605–625). Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Psillos, S. (2004). Inference to the best explanation and Bayesianism. In F. Stadler (Ed.), Induction and deduction in the sciences (pp. 83–91). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Psillos, S. (2009). Knowing the structure of nature: Essays on realism and explanation. Houndmills: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach, H. (1938). Experience and prediction. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. (1990). Rationality and objectivity in science or Tom Kuhn meets Tom Bayes. In C. W. Savage (Ed.), Scientific theories (pp. 175–204). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. (2001a). Explanation and confirmation: A Bayesian critique of inference to the best explanation. In Hon & Rakover (Eds.), pp. 61–91.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shimony, A. (1970). Scientific inference. In R. G. Colodny (Ed.), The nature and function of scientific theories (pp. 79–172). Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (2015). Ockham’s Razor: A user’s manual. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stanford, P. K. (2006). Exceeding our grasp: Science, history, and the problem of unconceived alternatives. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P. (1978). The best explanation: Criteria for theory choice. The Journal of Philosophy, 75, 76–92.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P. (1989). Explanatory coherence. Behavioural and Brain Sciences, 12 (03), 435-502.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tuomela, R. (1985). Truth and best explanation. Erkenntnis, 22, 271–299.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B. (1989). Laws and symmetry. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, J. (2009). Locating IBE in the Bayesian framework. Synthese, 167, 125–143.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Niiniluoto, I. (2018). Inference to the Best Explanation. In: Truth-Seeking by Abduction. Synthese Library, vol 400. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-99157-3_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics