Skip to main content

Explanationist Evidentialism: A Defense

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Believing in Accordance with the Evidence

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 398))

Abstract

In this chapter I defend Explanationist Evidentialism, the theory developed and argued for in Evidentialism and Epistemic Justification, from the objections raised by Richard Fumerton, Jonathan Kvanvig, and Matthias Steup. Ultimately, I conclude that although each of these philosophers presents interesting challenges, none of the challenges succeed in undermining Explanationist Evidentialism. It remains a viable theory of epistemic justification:

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See my (2013, 2014a, b, 2015, 2016, 2017, and 2018a, b).

  2. 2.

    Those chapters, as well as this one, grew out of a 2016 Pacific APA symposium on Evidentialism and Epistemic Justification.

  3. 3.

    See, especially, Conee and Feldman (1985, 2004, 2008, and 2011).

  4. 4.

    It is worth noting that this formulation is slightly different from what is presented in my (2014a). I have replaced “logical consequence” with “explanatory consequence” here. I explain the reasons for this in my (2015).

  5. 5.

    Footnote 4 applies here as well.

  6. 6.

    This is assuming an internalist view of epistemic justification, which both Fumerton and I are happy to do. Externalists may be able to avoid claiming that more is required. For example, a reliabilist can deny that one even needs to be directly aware of the pain experience. Instead, they can claim that as long as the pain belief is the result of a reliable belief forming process it is justified. Nevertheless, even a reliabilist will have to acknowledge that one needs to possess the concepts required for grasping the believed proposition in order to have a justified introspective belief.

  7. 7.

    See Fumerton (2005, 125) where he argues in support of the importance of distinguishing these states when considering instances of justified introspective beliefs.

  8. 8.

    I explore this promising combination in my (2018a).

  9. 9.

    I have argued that epistemic conservatism is much more plausible than is often thought in my (2008) and (Forthcoming-a). I also argue that it is perfectly consistent with an evidentialist conception of epistemic justification in my (Forthcoming-b).

  10. 10.

    See Poston (2014) for a coherentist view that is very similar to EE.

  11. 11.

    Such a view bears some resemblance to earlier explanationist views like those of Elgin (1996), Lycan (1988), and Harman (1973, 1986).

  12. 12.

    I discuss this in much more detail in my (2018a).

  13. 13.

    See BonJour (1998) and my (2016) for more on this. See Huemer (2009) and Poston (2014) for arguments making similar claims related to Goodman’s new riddle of induction.

  14. 14.

    The example that follows is similar to one I describe elsewhere (2016, 195).

  15. 15.

    In my previous work I referred to this view as “Psychologism”, but I will follow Kvanvig in calling it “Statism”.

  16. 16.

    See Turri (2009) for discussion of this problem and others for Propositionalism.

  17. 17.

    I don’t respond to Steup’s third ground for his criticism, what he calls the “Missing Causal Connection Problem”, because I have addressed this worry in other recent work. See my (2015) and (2017).

  18. 18.

    I hesitate to agree with Steup about the plausibility of analyzing availability in terms of what S believes because it seems that restricting explanations that provide justification to the best sufficiently good available explanation may avoid the worries he raises. This sort of restriction is motivated by independent reasons (see my (2015, 2016, 2017, and 2018b)).

  19. 19.

    Likewise, p’s being available as an explanatory consequence should be understood in terms of S’s being disposed to have a particular seeming on the basis of reflection alone.

  20. 20.

    See Poston (2014) for discussion of the importance of explanatory power as a virtue. Also, see my (2014a, 2015, 2016, and 2017).

  21. 21.

    Thanks to Kevin Lee, Scott Stapleford, and Siddharth Srikakolapu for helpful comments on earlier drafts. And, a very special thanks to Richard Fumerton, Jon Kvanvig, and Matthias Steup. I am honored that they took the time to read my book and write such thoughtful commentaries.

References

  • BonJour, L. (1998). In defense of pure reason: A rationalist account of a priori justification. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Conee, E., & Feldman, R. (1985). Evidentialism. Philosophical Studies, 45, 15–34.

    Google Scholar 

  • Conee, E., & Feldman, R. (2004). Making sense of skepticism. In E. Conee & R. Feldman (Eds.), Evidentialism (pp. 277–206). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Conee, E., & Feldman, R. (2008). Evidence. In Q. Smith (Ed.), Epistemology: New essays (pp. 83–104). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Conee, E., & Feldman, R. (2011). Replies. In T. Dougherty (Ed.), Evidentialism and its discontents (pp. 428–501). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elgin, C. Z. (1996). Considered judgment. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fumerton, R. (1980). Induction and reasoning to the best explanation. Philosophy of Science, 47, 589–600.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fumerton, R. (1995). Metaepistemology and skepticism. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fumerton, R. (2005). Speckled hens and objects of acquaintance. Philosophical Perspectives, 19, 121–138.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fumerton, R. (2017). Reasoning to the best explanation. In K. McCain & T. Poston (Eds.), Best explanations: New essays on inference to the best explanation (pp. 65–69). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (1973). Thought. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (1986). Change in view. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huemer, M. (2009). Explanationist aid for the theory of inductive logic. British Journal of Philosophy of Science, 60, 345–375.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (2010). In T. L. Beauchamp (Ed.), An enquiry concerning human understanding. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lycan, W. G. (1988). Judgement and justification. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCain, K. (2008). The virtues of epistemic conservatism. Synthese, 164, 185–200.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCain, K. (2013). Explanationist evidentialism. Episteme, 10, 299–315.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCain, K. (2014a). Evidentialism and epistemic justification. New York: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McCain, K. (2014b). Evidentialism, explanationism, and beliefs about the future. Erkenntnis, 79, 99–109.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCain, K. (2015). Explanationism: Defended on all sides. Logos & Episteme, 6, 333–349.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCain, K. (2016). The nature of scientific knowledge: An explanatory approach (p. 2016). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McCain, K. (2017). Undaunted explanationism. Logos & Episteme, 8, 117–127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCain, K. (2018a). Explanationist aid for phenomenal conservatism. Synthese, 195, 3035–3050.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCain, K. (2018b). Explanatory virtues are indicative of truth. Logos & Episteme, 9, 63–73.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCain, K. (Forthcoming-a). Epistemic conservatism and the basing relation. In P. Bondy & J. A. Carter (Eds), Well-founded belief: New essays on the epistemic basing relation. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCain, K. (Forthcoming-b). Epistemic conservatism: A non-evidentialist epistemology? In L. Moretti & N. Pedersen (Eds.), Non-evidentialist epistemology. Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Poston, T. (2014). Reason & explanation: A defense of explanatory coherentism. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Turri, J. (2009). The ontology of epistemic reasons. Nous, 43, 490–512.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Kevin McCain .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer International Publishing AG, part of Springer Nature

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

McCain, K. (2018). Explanationist Evidentialism: A Defense. In: McCain, K. (eds) Believing in Accordance with the Evidence. Synthese Library, vol 398. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-95993-1_22

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics