Skip to main content

Foundationalism and Coherentism

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Epistemic Relativism and Scepticism
  • 263 Accesses

Abstract

This chapter examines two classic responses to the epistemic regress problem: foundationalism and coherentism. Foundationalists seek to avoid the regress by invoking the non-inferential justification of basic beliefs, while coherentists do so by introducing a non-linear conception of justification. While both of these positions focus on the possibility of justifying beliefs, neither of them can establish the trustworthiness of basic epistemic methods without relying on the outcomes of those same methods. On a strictly internalist view, this means that neither of them can successfully answer the Agrippan argument that motivates Pyrrhonian scepticism and epistemic relativism. Furthermore, they both posit subjective, variable sources of justification—acquaintance and coherence—which reinforces the case for epistemic relativism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Epistemic internalism is the view that the factors responsible for a belief’s justification are internal to the believer, such that the believer has mental access to those factors. Common internalist candidates for justifiers include: evidence, reasons, arguments, and mental states.

  2. 2.

    For influential accounts of rational intuition as a source of non-inferential justification, see Bealer (1992) and BonJour (1998).

  3. 3.

    BonJour and Fumerton defend similar versions of empirical foundationalism in DePaul (2001). See also BonJour (1999a, b) and Fumerton (1995).

  4. 4.

    It is important to note that this is not a species of relative justification for foundationalists, since experiences and intuitions are not part of our epistemic system, i.e., they are neither beliefs nor methods, and therefore, foundationalists are not claiming that the justification of basic beliefs is system-relative. Indeed, experiences and intuitions are supposed to provide an absolute justification for basic beliefs that does not depend on one’s other commitments. In the following section, I argue that strictly internalist foundationalists cannot successfully argue for this conclusion, and in Sect. 4.2.4, I argue that foundationalism collapses into epistemic relativism if experiences and intuitions are subjective and variable, as they seem to be.

  5. 5.

    Some claim that this condition, or something akin to it, is a “core tenet” of internalism (Van Cleve 2003, 45). There are, however, self-professed internalists who reject it, such as Chisholm (1982) and Boghossian (2001). For internalists who do endorse this requirement, see BonJour (1980), Lehrer (1990), and Fumerton (1995).

  6. 6.

    It has been argued that Descartes himself is not actually caught in the Cartesian circle because, unlike Arnault, he rejects (KC) (Van Cleve 1979). This response to the problem of the criterion will be discussed at length in the next chapter. There is a vast literature on the problem of epistemic circularity , beginning with (Alston 1986).

  7. 7.

    On this point, see Lemos (2004, 261).

  8. 8.

    More specifically, their being unjustified is incompatible with our knowing that a method is a source of internalist justification, such as evidence, reasons, arguments, or mental states.

  9. 9.

    Carroll’s “What the Tortoise Said to Achilles” (1895) nicely illustrates this point. See also Boghossian (2000).

  10. 10.

    On this point, see Putnam (1978). Barnes and Bloor (1982, 40–42) use the inevitable circularity involved in justifying MP as a crucial component in their argument for the relativity of logical knowledge.

  11. 11.

    Stich (1990) makes a similar point in favour of his brand of relativism.

  12. 12.

    This coherentist response to scepticism was first presented in Bosanquet (1920). See also BonJour (1985, Chap. 5).

  13. 13.

    For a defense of this view, see Kitcher (1982, 2007).

  14. 14.

    For instances of these coherentist positions, see Ewing (1934), Lewis (1946), and Thagard (2000), respectively.

  15. 15.

    For more on the problem that memory poses for coherentism , see BonJour (1999b, 130) and Van Cleve (2005, 174).

  16. 16.

    Hales (2006, 79) provides the following example: “The Catholic worldview is as meticulous and all-encompassing as the most ambitious philosophical system, indicating that belief-sets resulting from revelation fare quite well by the standards of comprehensiveness, consistency, explanatoriness and similar criteria.”

  17. 17.

    Consider also Rorty ’s point, discussed in Sect. 3.4.3, that our understanding of the epistemic values that are constitutive of coherence—scope, accuracy, fruitfulness, consistency, and simplicity—is system-relative.

References

  • Alston, W. (1986). Epistemic circularity. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 47(1), 1–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barnes, B., & Bloor, D. (1982). Relativism, rationalism and the sociology of knowledge. In M. Hollis & S. Lukes (Eds.), Rationality and relativism (pp. 21–47). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bealer, G. (1992). The incoherence of empiricism. Aristotelian Society Supplementary, 66, 99–138.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boghossian, P. (2000). Knowledge of logic. In P. Boghossian & C. Peacocke (Eds.), New essays on the a priori (pp. 229–254). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Boghossian, P. (2001). How are objective reasons possible? Philosophical Studies, 106, 1–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • BonJour, L. (1980). Externalist theories of empirical knowledge. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 5(1), 53–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • BonJour, L. (1985). The structure of empirical knowledge. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • BonJour, L. (1998). In defense of pure reason. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • BonJour, L. (1999a). Foundationalism and the external world. Philosophical Perspectives, 13, 229–249.

    Google Scholar 

  • BonJour, L. (1999b). The dialectic of foundationalism and coherentism. In J. Greco & E. Sosa (Eds.), The Blackwell guide to epistemology (pp. 117–144). Malden, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bosanquet, B. (1920). Implication and linear inference. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carroll, L. (1895). What the tortoise said to Achilles. Mind, 4, 275–280.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chisholm, R. (1982). The problem of the criterion. In The foundations of knowing (pp. 61–75). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • DePaul, M. R. (2001). Resurrecting old-fashioned foundationalism (M. R. DePaul, Ed.). Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Descartes, R. (1641 [1984]). Meditations of first philosophy. In The philosophical writings of Descartes (Vol. II, pp. 1–383, J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff, & D. Murdoch, Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ewing, A. C. (1934). Idealism: A critical survey. London: Methuen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fumerton, R. (1995). Metaepistemology and skepticism. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fumerton, R. (2008). The problem of the criterion. In J. Greco (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of skepticism (pp. 34–52). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hales, S. D. (2006). Relativism and the foundations of philosophy. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (1740 [1975]). A treatise of human nature (L. A. Selby-Bigge, Ed., Second edition revised by P. H. Nidditch). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1982). Abusing science: The case against creationism. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (2007). Living with Darwin: Evolution, design, and the future of faith. Oxford: University of Oxford Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lehrer, K. (1990). Theory of knowledge. Boulder: Westview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lemos, N. (2004). Epistemic circularity again. Philosophical Issues, 14, 254–270.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, C. I. (1946). An analysis of knowledge and valuation. LaSalle: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1978). There is at least one a priori truth. Erkenntnis, 13, 153–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stich, S. (1990). The fragmentation of reason. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P. (2000). Coherence in thought and action. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Cleve, J. (1979). Foundationalism, epistemic principles, and the Cartesian circle. The Philosophical Review, 88(1), 55–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Cleve, J. (2003). Is knowledge easy or impossible? Externalism as the only answer to skepticism. In S. Luper (Ed.), The skeptics (pp. 45–59). Aldershot: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Cleve, J. (2005). Why coherence is not enough: A defense of moderate foundationalism. In M. Steup & E. Sosa (Eds.), Contemporary debates in epistemology (pp. 168–180). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, M. (2007). Why (Wittgensteinian) contextualism is not relativism. Episteme, 4(1), 93–114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wright, C. (2004). Warrant for nothing (and foundations for free?). The Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume, 78(1), 167–212.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Steven Bland .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Bland, S. (2018). Foundationalism and Coherentism. In: Epistemic Relativism and Scepticism. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-94673-3_4

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics