Skip to main content

Introduction

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Epistemic Relativism and Scepticism
  • 240 Accesses

Abstract

This chapter frames Pyrrhonian scepticism and epistemic relativism as meta-philosophical threats that rely on the same argument: the Agrippan trilemma. Philosophers have traditionally attempted to neutralize both threats by means of a common response to this argument. The chapter surveys a number of such responses before outlining a more promising, dialectical argument against epistemic relativism that has no anti-sceptical ambitions. In doing so, it elucidates the book’s central claim that Pyrrhonian scepticism and epistemic relativism are distinct threats that require different responses.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Rorty himself abjures the ‘relativist’ label in favour of ‘pragmatist’: “The charge that pragmatism is “relativistic” is simply [the traditional philosopher’s] first unthinking expression of disgust at a teaching which seems cynical about our deepest hopes” (Rorty 1980, 735). This is in no small part due to his uncharitable understanding of the relativist doctrine: “‘Relativism’ is the view that every belief on a certain topic, or perhaps about any topic, is as good as every other. No one holds this view” (Ibid., 727). Whatever Rorty wants to call himself—pragmatist, epistemic behaviourist, anti-foundationalist—he does seem to be an epistemic relativist on my understanding of this term, and on others’—see Rorty (1979, 178, 182, 212, 317, 329–330, 335, 361, 364–365, 377, 379, 385), as well as Haack (1993, Ch. 9), Boghossian (2006, Ch. 5), and Seidel (2014, Ch. 3).

  2. 2.

    For other discussions of the implications of epistemic relativism on philosophical methodology, see Hales (2006) and Carter (2016, Chs. 1 and 9).

  3. 3.

    See also Rorty (1979, 179).

  4. 4.

    Rorty goes further still, insisting that truth ought not to be the aim of inquiry (Rorty 1979, 377).

  5. 5.

    For an older, but no less authoritative expression of this view, see Quine (1969). More recently, Maddy (2007, Chapter I.2) has offered a similar view.

  6. 6.

    See also Sosa (1994).

References

  • Baghramian, M. (2004). Relativism. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boghossian, P. (2006). Fear of knowledge: Against relativism and constructivism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carter, J. A. (2016). Metaepistemology and relativism. Houndsmills, Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Haack, S. (1993). Evidence and inquiry. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hales, S. D. (2006). Relativism and the foundations of philosophy. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kornblith, H. (1999). In defense of naturalized epistemology. In J. Greco & E. Sosa (Eds.), The Blackwell guide to epistemology (pp. 158–169). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luper, S. (2004). Epistemic relativism. Philosophical Issues, 14, 271–295.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maddy, P. (2007). Second philosophy: A naturalistic method. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1969). Epistemology naturalized. In Ontological relativity and other essays (pp. 68–90). New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, R. (1979). Philosophy and the mirror of nature. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, R. (1980). Pragmatism, relativism, and irrationalism. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 53(6), 719–738.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sankey, H. (2012). Scepticism, relativism and the argument from the criterion. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science A, 43, 182–190.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Seidel, M. (2014). Epistemic relativism: A constructive critique. Houndsmills, Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sextus Empiricus. (2000). Outlines of scepticism (J. Annas & J. Barnes, Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. (1994). Philosophical scepticism and epistemic circularity. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 68(Suppl.), 263–290.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, M. (2007). Why (Wittgensteinian) contextualism is not relativism. Episteme, 4(1), 93–114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Steven Bland .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Bland, S. (2018). Introduction. In: Epistemic Relativism and Scepticism. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-94673-3_1

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics