Skip to main content

Technical Change and the Decentralization Penalty

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Social Design

Part of the book series: Studies in Economic Design ((DESI))

Abstract

We consider the organizer of a firm who compares a decentralized arrangement where divisions are granted total autonomy with a centralized arrangement where perfect monitoring and policing guarantee that all divisions make the choices the organizer wants them to make. We ask: when does improvement in the divisions’ technology strengthen the case for decentralization and when does it weaken it? In a simple one-division model with complete information and linear contracts we obtain conditions under which the welfare loss due to decentralizing rises (falls) when technology improves.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    A variety of social situations are studied from this point of view. One of them concerns optimal versus “selfish” routing in transportation (Roughgarden, 2005). Others are found in Nissan et al. (2007). Many of these studies develop bounds on the price of anarchy. Several of them (e.g., Balbaieff et al. 2009) consider a Principal/Agent setting.

  2. 2.

    Surveys of the design literature with communication and computation costs are found in Garicano and Prat (2013) and Marschak (2006). A model in which revenue is shared by a group of game-playing Agents is studied in Courtney and Marschak (2009). Each player chooses effort and bears its cost. Equilibria of the game are compared with the welfare-maximizing efforts. The paper finds conditions under which the welfare loss drops (rises) when effort costs shift down.

  3. 3.

    The derivative is \(\hat {x}_t(r,t) \cdot [rR'(\hat {x}(r,t))-t \cdot C'(\hat {x}(r,t))]-C(\hat {x}(r,t))\). That is negative, since 0 < r < 1 and \(\hat {x}(r,t)\) satisfies the first-order condition 0 = rR′− tC′.

  4. 4.

    The derivative is negative if Ar 2 > t ⋅ (2r − 1). That is the case at r = 0 and at r = 1 (since t < A). At all r ∈ (0, 1), our requirement t < Ar implies that 2Ar, the derivative of the left side of the inequality with respect to r, exceeds 2t, the derivative of the right side. So, at all (r, t) ∈ Γ the inequality holds.

  5. 5.

    The details of this calculation, as well as a graph of effort gap and surplus gap, are given in LMW (2017). Details for the remaining examples are given there as well.

  6. 6.

    Once again, the details are in LMW.

  7. 7.

    See, for example, Sundaram (1996).

  8. 8.

    As already noted, the proofs of the parts not shown are given in LMW.

  9. 9.

    The details are provided in LMW.

References

  • Balbaieff, M., Feldman, M., & Nisan, N. (2009). Free riding and free labor in combinatorial agency. In M. Mavronicolas & V. G. Papadopoulou (Eds.), SDAGT 2009: Vol. 5814. Lecture Notes in Computer Science (pp. 109–121). Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Balmaceda, F., Balseiro, S., Correa, J., & Stier-Moses, N. (2016). Bounds on the welfare loss from moral hazard with limited liability. Games and Economic Behavior, 95, 137–155.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Courtney, D., & Marschak, T. (2009). Inefficiency and complementarity in sharing games. Review of Economic Design, 13, 7–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garicano, L., & Prat, A. (2013). Organizational economics with cognitive costs. In Advances in economics and econometrics: Theory and applications, proceedings of the tenth world congress of the econometric society. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grossman, S., & Hart, O. (1983). An analysis of the principal-agent problem. Econometrica, 51, 7–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holmstrom, B. (1979). Moral hazard and observability. The Bell Journal of Economics, 10, 74–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holmstrom, B. (1982). Moral hazard in teams. The Bell Journal of Economics, 13, 324–340.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hurwicz, L., & Shapiro, L. (1978). Incentive structures maximizing residual gain under incomplete information. The Bell Journal of Economics, 9, 180–191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Liang, R., Marschak, T., & Wei, D. (2017). Technological improvement and the decentralization penalty in a simple principal/agent model, SSRN e-library, 2945702 [Abbreviated as LMW in the text].

    Google Scholar 

  • Marschak, T. (2006). Organization structure. In T. Hendershott (Ed.), Handbook of economics and information systems (pp. 205–290). New York: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nasri, M., Bastin, F., & Marcotte, P. (2015). Quantifying the social welfare loss in moral hazard models. European Journal of Operations Research, 245, 226–235.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nissan,N., Roughgarden, T., Tardos, E., & Vazirani, V. (2007). Algorithmic game theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ross, S. (1973). The economic theory of agency: The principal’s problem. American Economic Review, 63, 134–139.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roughgarden, T. (2005). Selfish routing and the price of anarchy. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sundaram, R. K. (1996). A first course in optimization theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Thomas Marschak .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Appendix

Appendix

1.1 Proofs of Parts (a), (g), and (h) of Theorem 1

1.1.1 Proof of Part (a)

The function r ⋅ R(x) − tC(x), where t is fixed, displays strictly increasing differences in r, x if r ⋅ R(x) displays strictly increasing differences in r, x. But that is the case, since R is nondecreasing. Since, for fixed t, the effort \(\hat {x}(r,t)\) maximizes r ⋅ R(x) − tC(x) on the effort set Σ, it is indeed the case that \(\hat {x}(r_H,t) \geq \hat {x}(r_L,t)\), as (a) asserts. Part (a) also asserts that the Agent strictly prefers the higher share. That is the case since \(\hat {x}(r_H,t)\) is a maximizer of r H ⋅ R(x) − t ⋅ C(x), so we have

$$\displaystyle \begin{aligned} r_H \cdot R(\hat{x}(r_H,t))-t \cdot C (\hat{x}(r_H,t))&\geq r_H \cdot R(\hat{x}(r_L,t))-t \cdot C (\hat{x}(r_L,t))\\ &> r_H \cdot R(\hat{x}(r_L,t))-t \cdot C (\hat{x}(r_L,t)). \end{aligned} $$

1.1.2 Proof of Part (g)

Part (g) says:

$$\displaystyle \begin{aligned}W(r,t_L) > W(r,t_H) \mbox{ whenever }t_L,t_H \in \tilde{\Gamma} \mbox{and }0<t_L<t_H.\end{aligned}$$

The effort \(\hat {x}(r,t_L)\) is a maximizer of rR(x) − t H ⋅ C(x). Hence,

$$\displaystyle \begin{aligned}r \cdot R(\hat{x}(r,t_L))-t_L \cdot C(\hat{x}(r,t_L)) \geq r \cdot R(\hat{x}(r,t_H))-t_L \cdot C(\hat{x}(r,t_H))\end{aligned}$$

or

$$\displaystyle \begin{aligned}r \cdot [R(\hat{x}(r,t_L))-R(\hat{x}(r,t_H))] \geq t_L \cdot [C(\hat{x}(r,t_L))-C(\hat{x}(r,t_H))].\end{aligned}$$

That implies—since 0 < r < 1—that

$$\displaystyle \begin{aligned}R(\hat{x}(r,t_L))-R(\hat{x}(r,t_H)) > t_L \cdot [C(\hat{x}(r,t_L))-C(\hat{x}(r,t_H))]\end{aligned}$$

or

$$\displaystyle \begin{aligned}R(\hat{x}(r,t_L))-t_L \cdot C(\hat{x}(r,t_L)) >R(\hat{x}(r,t_H))-t_L \cdot C(\hat{x}(r,t_H))\end{aligned}$$

and hence (since t H > t L)

$$\displaystyle \begin{aligned}R(\hat{x}(r,t_L))-t_L \cdot C(\hat{x}(r,t_L)) >R(\hat{x}(r(t_H),t_H))-t_H \cdot C(\hat{x}(r,t_H))\end{aligned}$$

The term on the left of the inequality is W(r, t L) and the term on the right is W(r, t H). That completes the proof of Part (g).

1.1.3 Proof of Part (h)

When the Agent’s share is r H, he chooses an effort \(\hat {x}(r_H,t)\) which satisfies

$$\displaystyle \begin{aligned}r_H R(\hat{x}(r_H,t))-tC(\hat{x}(r_H,t))\geq r_H R(\hat{x}(r_L,t))-tC(\hat{x}(r_L,t)),\end{aligned}$$

or equivalently

$$\displaystyle \begin{aligned} r_H \cdot \left[R(\hat{x}(r_H,t))-R(\hat{x}(r_L,t))\right]\geq t \cdot \left[C(\hat{x}(r_H,t))-C(\hat{x}(r_L,t))\right]. \end{aligned} $$
(1)

Part (a) of Theorem 1 tells us that \(\hat {x}(r_H,t) \geq \hat {x}(r_L,t)\). Since R is strictly increasing, that means that the left side of (1) is either positive or zero. First, suppose that it is positive. Then, since r H < 1, (1) implies that

$$\displaystyle \begin{aligned} R(\hat{x}(r_H,t))-R(\hat{x}(r_L,t)) > t \cdot \left[C(\hat{x}(r_H,t))-C(\hat{x}(r_L,t))\right], \end{aligned} $$
(2)

or equivalently

$$\displaystyle \begin{aligned} R(\hat{x}(r_H,t))- t \cdot C(\hat{x}(r_H,t))> R(\hat{x}(r_L,t))- t \cdot C(\hat{x}(r_L,t)),\end{aligned} $$
(3)

i.e.,

$$\displaystyle \begin{aligned} W(r_H,t) > W(r_L,t).\end{aligned} $$
(4)

If \(\hat {x}(r_H,t) \neq \hat {x}(r_L,t)\), then, since R is strictly increasing, the left side of (1) is indeed positive, so (4) holds. If, on the other hand, \(\hat {x}(r_H,t) = \hat {x}(r_L,t)\), then both sides of (1) equal zero and (2),(3),(4) become equalities. So, as claimed, W(r H, t) ≥ W(r L, t) and the inequality is strict if and only if \(\hat {x}(r_H,t) \neq \hat {x}(r_L,t)\).

1.2 Proofs of Parts (a) and (b) of Theorem 2

1.2.1 Proof of Part (a)

We note first that the Agent’s chosen effort \(\hat {x}(r,t)\) depends only on the ratio \({r \over t}\), which we shall call ρ. The set of possible values of ρ is \(\left (0, {1 \over t} \right ]\). The Agent’s effort is a value of x which maximizes t ⋅ (ρR(x) − C(x)) on the effort set Σ and is therefore a maximizer of ρR(x) − C(x). We shall use a new symbol, namely ϕ(ρ) to denote the Agent’s chosen effort when the ratio is ρ. So, \(\phi (\rho )= \hat {x}(r,t)\). The function ρR(x) − C(x) displays strictly increasing differences with respect to ρ, x. Hence, the maximizer ϕ(ρ) is nondecreasing in ρ, so we have

$$\displaystyle \begin{aligned} \phi(\rho_H) \geq \phi(\rho_L) \mbox{ whenever }0<\rho_L<\rho_H. \end{aligned} $$
(+)

We can now reinterpret the Principal as the chooser of a ratio. For a given t, he chooses the ratio \(\rho ^{*}(t)={r^{*}(t) \over t}\), where

$$\displaystyle \begin{aligned}\rho^{*}(t)= \min \{\mbox{argmax}_{\rho \in (0,1/t)}~ M(\rho, -t)~ \},\end{aligned} $$

and

$$\displaystyle \begin{aligned}M(\rho, -t) = (1-t\rho) \cdot R(\phi (\rho)) = R(\phi(\rho)) -t \cdot \rho \cdot R(\phi(\rho)).\end{aligned} $$

The function M has strictly increasing differences in ρ, −t if the function − t ⋅ ρ ⋅ R(ϕ(ρ)) has strictly increasing differences in ρ, −t. But that is the case, since R is nondecreasing, which implies (using (+)) that R(ϕ( ⋅ )) is also nondecreasing. Since ρ (t) is a maximizer of M(ρ, −t), we conclude that

$$\displaystyle \begin{aligned}{r^{*}(t_L) \over t_L} =\rho^{*}(t_L) \geq \rho^{*}(t_H) ={r^{*}(t_H) \over t_H} \mbox{ whenever }0<t_L<t_H,\end{aligned} $$

as Part (a) asserts.

1.2.2 Proof of Part (b)

We use the terminology just used in the proof of Part (a). Since \(\phi \left ({r^{*}(t) \over t} \right )= \hat {x}(r^{*}(t),t)\), we have, using (+) in the proof of part (a), \(\hat {x}(r^{*}(t_L),t_L) \geq \hat {x}(r^{*}(t_H),t_H)\), as (b) asserts.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Marschak, T., Wei, D. (2019). Technical Change and the Decentralization Penalty. In: Trockel, W. (eds) Social Design. Studies in Economic Design. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-93809-7_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics