Skip to main content

The Core Expressivist Manoeuvre

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Metaepistemology

Part of the book series: Palgrave Innovations in Philosophy ((PIIP))

  • 390 Accesses

Abstract

Critical engagements with expressivism exhibit a familiar pattern. A critic presses an objection against the view, while those sympathetic with expressivism respond that the critic has fundamentally misunderstood the view. Some philosophers, myself included, have contended that epistemic expressivism is vulnerable to some important objections with which expressivists must grapple. Predictably, those sympathetic with expressivism have responded that these objections miss the mark because they work with a mistaken understanding of the expressivist project. The purpose of this chapter is to examine the contention that a methodological strategy—what J. Adam Carter and Matthew Chrisman call the core expressivist manoeuvre—enables expressivism to sidestep a host of objections levelled against the view. I contend that extant versions of expressivism are poorly situated to execute this manoeuvre and, so, expressivists are presently not well-situated to appeal to the core manoeuvre in order to avoid certain types of theoretical burdens and deflect various types of criticisms of their view.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 119.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Here is a representative passage: “As we see things, the core expressivist maneuver involves changing the question from one about the nature of epistemic facts or values to one about the nature of epistemic evaluations. Once an expressivist has given his answer to the new question by insisting on a disanalogy between epistemic thought and discourse and descriptive thought and discourse, and once he has argued that this answer undermines the first question…[which is] a question about the nature of some feature of the world whose existence is disputed: epistemic facts or values … he can just stop talking (at least in the capacity of stating his theory)” (Carter and Chrisman 2012, 334).

  2. 2.

    See Schroeder (2008a, 151, b, 8). Cp. also what Dreier (2015) calls the “Expressivist Sidestep”.

  3. 3.

    According to Carter and Chrisman, the objectors to whom they are responding “each misunderstand what is crucial to epistemic expressivism” (2012, 334).

  4. 4.

    I am working, then, with a fairly broad characterisation of the normative. But it does mirror that offered by expressivists such as Ridge (2014, chap. 1). If one wishes, one can think of the normative more narrowly as some subset of the normative, such as what is decisively reason-giving. In what follows, I remain neutral regarding the relations these different dimensions of the normative bear to one another.

  5. 5.

    In principle, one could understand this project broadly (so that it concerns any attempt to answer the questions above) or narrowly (so that it concerns only certain kinds of attempts to answer these questions, such as those that concern properties and facts that are “substantive”). I understand the project broadly. My reason for doing so is that, even under a narrow understanding of the project, expressivists will face questions that appear to belong to the metaphysical project, and which they seem interested in side-stepping.

  6. 6.

    Carter and Chrisman (2012, 334–35). Although see Chrisman (2011) for a somewhat different approach.

  7. 7.

    As for the “proper aims” of metanormative inquiry, I’ll remain neutral regarding exactly what they are and how to substantiate them.

  8. 8.

    As Schroeder (2008a, 151, b, 8) emphasises.

  9. 9.

    Parfit (2011, 408–10, 2017, 191) retracts this charge.

  10. 10.

    In Cuneo (2007, chap. 6). Carter and Chrisman (2012) engage with one argument I offer against expressivism.

  11. 11.

    The two passages in which something akin to the core maneuver is most explicitly voiced are Gibbard (2003, 6) and Blackburn (1999, 50).

  12. 12.

    Carter and Chrisman (2012, 334 n8) offer a reading of what expressivists have in mind when they talk about “deflated” normative facts.

  13. 13.

    I borrow the terminology from Alston (1999, chap. 4). To commit oneself to being in a mental state does not imply that one is in such a state. There can be commitments that are insincere or mistaken.

  14. 14.

    In Cuneo (2014), I develop an argument for the conclusion that normative facts are among those that explain how it is that we could speak. An implication of that argument is that, even if expressivism were to offer a correct description of how normative thought and discourse typically functions, normative facts play crucial explanatory roles ; see Cuneo (2014, chap. 6).

  15. 15.

    They might play other interesting explanatory roles too, as Sturgeon (1985, 1992) contends.

  16. 16.

    I assume this is what Gibbard means by “imperatives.” Chrisman (2016, 131) includes an illuminating discussion regarding such contents.

  17. 17.

    Ridge (2014) is the most developed version of the view. I find no indications in Ridge’s discussion that he endorses the core maneuver.

  18. 18.

    In his development of standards expressivism, Ridge (2014, 27–28) offers an even more nuanced account of directives, maintaining (inter alia) that the normative modal “must” adverts to context-specific standards that require, while the normative modal “ought” adverts to context-specific standards that recommend. So, under Ridge’s view, it is no surprise that we can move fluidly between sentences such as “You are required to ϕ” and “You must ϕ!”.

  19. 19.

    This denial concerns the deep structure of normative thought and discourse. See Blackburn (1993, 184–85). Expressivism’s advocates sometimes point out that it would not be inaccurate to say that such thought and discourse have predicative normative representational content, provided that we are speaking only of the surface structure of such thought and discourse or, alternatively, that we have some sufficiently deflated sense of predication or representation in mind. For the point about surface structure, see Blackburn (1993, 157, 185); for the point about deflationism, see Blackburn (1999, chap. 3).

  20. 20.

    Some content Φ’s being about x does not entail that x exists, is actual, or is instantiated. For example, thoughts about unicorns represent unicorns, though there are no such creatures.

  21. 21.

    So, when Gibbard writes that, given his norm expressivism, the “main thing to be explained is not what a norm is, but what ‘accepting a norm is’,” (1990, 46) it is natural to be puzzled. Given his views about imperatival contents, it makes perfect sense to ask questions about the ontological status of these norms and what they represent, if they have some source, what it would be for one set to be correct, and how they could be “natural,” as Gibbard claims. These are the very sorts of questions at issue in the metaphysical project. Their answers are open to a variety of concerns and objections.

  22. 22.

    See the references supplied by Chrisman (2016, sec. 5.3). A crucial component of the expressivist semantics that Schroeder develops are mistake conditions (2008a, chap. 10). When assessing this proposal, Schroeder writes that any expressivist view will have to explain what mistakes are in the relevant sense (2008a, 168).

  23. 23.

    Interestingly, when Chrisman offers an example of such an account, he does so by appealing to mere imperatives devoid of deontic modals.

  24. 24.

    Copp (1995, 2007) are exceptions. In his (2007), Copp writes that standards are the “semantic contents expressed by imperatives, and so they are not believed, nor do they represent the world as being one way or another.” (14) I am not sure why Copp maintains that imperatives fail to represent the world as being one way or another.

  25. 25.

    See, for example, Wedgwood’s (2007, pt. 1) discussion of normative concepts and Cuneo and Shafer-Landau’s (2014) discussion of moral concepts.

  26. 26.

    There is a limited effort to extend the account to the category of reasons; see Gibbard’s (2003, 188–91) discussion of reasons and Ridge’s (2014, chap. 1) critique.

  27. 27.

    To be clear, Gibbard takes the planning-state approach and standards expressivism to be complementary. But, as best I can tell, he does not explain how to mesh the two approaches. The worry is that any attempt to combine them would lack the requisite theoretical unity.

  28. 28.

    Recall it is this: an act “might be N-permitted without being rational, for the system N might have little recommend it.” (1990, 87) But the same is true of endorsements. Many have little to recommend them. So, if this is Gibbard’s rationale for rejecting the factualist account of normativity, it is also a rationale for rejecting the account he offers.

  29. 29.

    Chrisman (2016) offers an inferentialist proposal regarding “ought.” As best I can tell, there is no discussion of whether the approach could be generalised to all normative modals.

  30. 30.

    Thanks to Adam Carter, Matthew Chrisman, Tyler Doggett, and the UVM Ethics Reading Group for their comments on a draft of this essay.

References

  • Alston, William. 1999. Illocutionary Acts and Sentence Meaning. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blackburn, Simon. 1980. Spreading the Word. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1993. Moral Realism. In Essays in Quasi-Realism, ed. Simon Blackburn, 111–129. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1999. Ruling Passions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carter, J. Adam, and Matthew Chrisman. 2012. Is Epistemic Expressivism Incompatible with Inquiry? Philosophical Studies 159 (3): 323–339.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chrisman, Matthew. 2011. Ethical Expressivism. In The Continuum Companion to Ethics, ed. Christian Miller, 29–54. New York: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2016. The Meaning of “Ought”: Beyond Descriptivism and Expressivism in Metaethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Copp, David. 1995. Morality, Normativity, and Society. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2007. Morality in a Natural World: Selected Essays in Metaethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cuneo, Terence. 2007. The Normative Web: An Argument for Moral Realism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014. Speech and Morality: On the Metaethical Implications of Speaking. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cuneo, Terence, and Russ Shafer-Landau. 2014. The Moral Fixed Points: New Directions for Moral Nonnaturalism. Philosophical Studies 171 (3): 399–443.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dreier, James. 2004. Metaethics and the Problem of Creeping Minimalism. Philosophical Perspectives 18 (1): 23–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2015. Explaining the Quasi-Real. In Oxford Studies in Metaethics, ed. Russ Shafer-Landau, vol. 10, 273–298. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gibbard, Allan. 1990. Wise Choices, Apt Feelings. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2003. Thinking How to Live. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, Derek. 2017. On What Matters Vol. 3. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ridge, Michael. 2014. Impassioned Belief. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2015. I Might Be Fundamentally Mistaken. Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 9 (3): 1–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schroeder, Mark. 2008a. Being For. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2008b. Noncognitivism in Ethics. Abingdon: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sturgeon, Nicholas. 1985. Moral Explanations. In Morality, Reason and Truth, ed. David Copp and David Zimmerman, 49–78. Totowa, NJ: Rowman and Allanheld.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1992. Nonmoral Explanations. In Philosophical Perspectives 6: Ethics, ed. James Tomberlin, 97–117. Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wedgwood, Ralph. 2007. The Nature of Normativity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Terence Cuneo .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Cuneo, T. (2018). The Core Expressivist Manoeuvre. In: Kyriacou, C., McKenna, R. (eds) Metaepistemology. Palgrave Innovations in Philosophy. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-93369-6_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics