Skip to main content

Moral Expertise: A Comparative Philosophical Approach

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Book cover Moral Expertise

Part of the book series: Philosophy and Medicine ((PHME,volume 129))

  • 327 Accesses

Abstract

Discussion of moral expertise typically ask whether knowledge of moral theory allows someone to make better moral judgments than those unversed in such theories, or at least to make sound judgments more reliably. This paper challenges a common assumption that real world moral judgments can be best understood as applications of a specific area of theoretical knowledge, rather in the way that engineering can be understood as a kind of applied physics. I challenge this assumption by drawing on the work of the comparative philosopher Thomas Kasulis to argue that a) moral wisdom is best understood as embodied in practices that do not readily admit of explicit discursive analysis, and b) such practices are themselves embedded in specific cultural traditions, so that c) moral expertise is realized in expertise and familiarity with culturally embedded behaviors. Consequently, moral expertise—even in an applied setting such as bioethics—is more akin to understanding classical ballet than knowing the principles and applications of a theoretical science. As an illustration, I then consider the classical Confucian idea of li, or ritual propriety, and its role in defining moral wisdom. I end by arguing that the appeals to specific cultural practices in this account does not entail relativism or subjectivism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See for example, Peter Singer (1972), pp. 115–117, for an argument that philosophers can be moral experts by virtue of their expertise in moral philosophy. For an argument against Singer that accepts the same terms of debate, see David Archard (2011).

  2. 2.

    See Gilbert Ryle (1949). It should be noted that Sellers was anticipated in drawing this distinction by John Dewey. See Hubert L. Dreyfus for discussion of Dewey’s early contribution to the idea that moral knowledge is a kind of knowledge-how.

  3. 3.

    For a particularly rich discussion of the ways in which knowledge that and knowledge how can be woven together see Christopher Winch (2010), Chap. 2.

  4. 4.

    Thomas Kasulis (2002), p. 133.

  5. 5.

    Kasulis, (2002), pp. 59–60.

  6. 6.

    Kasulis (2002), pg. 60.

  7. 7.

    These cultural contrasts are heavily qualified—Kasulis stresses that no culture can be exclusively characterized using either of the orientations and that there can be subcultures that are dominated by the orientation that is less prominent among the mainstream.

  8. 8.

    It is worth stressing that these remarks refer to broad characteristics of the more dominant theories of knowledge—traditions that arose in part in opposition to mainstream epistemology such as pragmatism and phenomenology arguably display greater affinities with an Intimacy orientation. Not surprisingly, many see points of convergence between these theories and classical Asian thought.

  9. 9.

    Kasulis (2002), p. 72.

  10. 10.

    Kasulis (2002), p. 78.

  11. 11.

    Indeed, insofar as knowledge that—scientific knowledge, for example—is generated through practices requiring skills born of experience and deepening familiarity, it too reflects elements of Intimacy. One learns how to be a scientist, or how to do science. The process by which scientific results are actually generated are indeed “dark” to the uninitiated, even if those results can be presented in ways that abstract away from their origins in the labs of practitioners.

  12. 12.

    Amy Olberding (2012), pp. 57. Olberding introduces the phrase “view of a life we should like” in contrast to an explicit and rigorous theory of human flourishing, something she concedes we do not find in early Confucian texts. The initial, intuitive idea such a theory is meant to elucidate and defend—that of a better, more satisfying and complete way of life—is what she means to capture in the idea of life we should like. A rich and compelling image of this, she argues, is what we find in text such as the Analects. Below I will also appeal to “flourishing”, but such appeals should also be understood in this pre-theoretical sense.

  13. 13.

    The classical Confucian moral imagination recognizes a higher type, the sheng ren, or sage, but such people are exceedingly rare, and this not a status we can realistically aspire to. Though later recognized as such, Confucius denied that he was sage and claims to have never met such a person—the sages he recognizes lived long ago.

  14. 14.

    As explained in the next paragraph, ren is translated in a variety of ways—I here defer to the more popular renderings, but there is much to be said for the alternatives introduced there.

  15. 15.

    Rogers T. Ames and Henry Rosemont Jr. (1999), 6.30.

  16. 16.

    Hence the link between ren and the virtues listed earlier. The cognitive dimension of ren points to the importance of knowledge and wisdom, or zhi, while the practical dimension points to the ability to translate such wisdom into effective action, or yi. All of this requires, in turn, a refinement of our moral sentiments: hence shu, zhong, and xin.

  17. 17.

    See for example, May Sim (2007) and Jiyuan Yu (2007).

  18. 18.

    Roger T. Ames and Henry Rosemont Jr. (1999) pp. 51.

  19. 19.

    Stephen C. Angle (2012), Chap. 6. See also Amy Olberding (2016).

  20. 20.

    Angle (2012) pg. 97. Angle argues this points to the need for a higher value—ren—that is distinct from and served by li. Angle concedes this is a somewhat controversial reading of Confucianism as some will argue li itself is the source of moral value in Confucianism. For reasons that will emerge in the next section, I side with Angle on this question. Angle also argues that Confucius is a bit unfair to the village worthy, as surely it is some kind of a mark of moral progress that one is willing and able to defer to moral standards even if it is for less that fully noble reasons. Indeed, a willingness to do so may be a necessary first step.

  21. 21.

    Olberding (2016) pp. 242.

  22. 22.

    Ames and Rosemont Jr. (1999) 2.4. Lest we think it is easy to become a junzi, Confucius notes that was not until he was 70 that he felt he had arrived. Hence the claim that it constitutes a kind of expertise.

  23. 23.

    If this sounds a little paradoxical, consider an example such a playing piano. Knowing how to play piano is embodied and displayed in somebody’s playing piano, but this is distinct from the musical qualities that are exemplified in accomplished performances. It is in reference to these that we judge this person’s piano playing or the value of different techniques, practice regimes, and so on. Expertise in playing piano is embodied in the playing but it is, as I have put it here, in service to the aesthetic properties on display in good playing.

  24. 24.

    Classical Confucianism itself can sometimes be criticized on these grounds as there is truth to the charge that its fondness for the social and cultural practices of the early Zhou Dynasty seems to rest on little more than its familiarity. On the other hand, the willingness to criticize practices current in the later Zhou, and the willingness of Confucius and others to embrace changes enacted since the early Zhou, suggest a recognition that that the li was not self legitimating.

  25. 25.

    See for example H.T. Engelhardt (2012). Similar points are made by a number of the essays collected in this volume.

  26. 26.

    American Society for Bioethics and Humanities (2011).

  27. 27.

    See for example, Edmund D. Pellegrino (1995). See also Edmund D. Pellegrino and David C. Thomasma (1993).

  28. 28.

    For an extended argument that Confucian ethical teaching was not the most compelling available in its own historical period, see Chad Hansen (2000).

  29. 29.

    Engelhardt (2012).

  30. 30.

    See Stephen Wear (2005). See also Lisa S. Parker (2005). Parker offers an account of ethical expertise that draws on Care Ethics in a way that I think resonates with the account offered here.

References

  • American Society for Bioethics and Humanities. 2011. Core competencies for health care ethics consultation: The report of the American Society for Bioethics and Humanities. 2nd ed. Glenview: American Society for Bioethics and Humanities.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ames, Roger T., and Rosemont Henry Jr. 1999. Introduction. In The analects of confucius: A philosophical translation. New York: Ballantine Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Angle, Stephen C. 2012. Contemporary Confucian political philosophy. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Archard, David. 2011. Why moral philosophers are not and should not be moral experts. Bioethics 25: 119–127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Engelhardt, H.T. 2012. A skeptical reassessment of ethics. In Bioethics critically reconsidered: Having second thoughts, ed. H.T. Englehardt. London: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hansen, Chad. 2000. A Daoist theory of Chinese thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kasulis, Thomas. 2002. Intimacy or integrity: Philosophy and cultural differences. Honolulu: University of Hawai’i Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Olberding, Amy. 2012. Moral exemplars in the analects: The good person is that. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2016. Etiquette: A confucian contribution to moral philosophy. Ethics 126: 422–446.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parker, Lisa S. 2005. Ethical expertise, maternal thinking and the work of clinical ethicists. In Ethics expertise: History, contemporary perspectives, and applications, ed. Lisa Rasmussen. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pellegrino, Edmund D. 1995. Towards a virtue-theory normative ethics for health professionals. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 5: 254–277.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pellegrino, Edmund D., and David C. Thomasma. 1993. The virtues in medical practice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, Gilbert. 1949. The concept of mind. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sim, May. 2007. Remastering morals with Aristotle and Confucius. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Singer, Peter. 1972. Moral experts. Analysis 32: 115–117.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wear, Stephen. 2005. Ethical expertise in the clinical setting. In Ethics expertise: History, contemporary perspectives, and applications, ed. Lisa Rasmussen. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winch, Christopher. 2010. Dimensions of expertise: A conceptual exploration of vocational knowledge. London: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yu, Jiyuan. 2007. The ethics of Confucius and Aristotle: Mirrors of Virtue. Oxford: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Dennis Arjo .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer International Publishing AG, part of Springer Nature

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Arjo, D. (2018). Moral Expertise: A Comparative Philosophical Approach. In: Watson, J., Guidry-Grimes, L. (eds) Moral Expertise. Philosophy and Medicine, vol 129. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-92759-6_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics