Advertisement

Demarcating Simulation

  • Nico Formanek
Chapter
Part of the Philosophy of Engineering and Technology book series (POET, volume 31)

Abstract

Philosophy of computer simulation has for long tried to answer the question: What makes computer simulation special? Answers normally proceed by giving a demarcation criterion, a property which only holds for computer simulation. The definition by demarcation has also been attempted in different fields, maybe most famously by Popper for science. So it might not come as a surprise that philosophy of mathematics has tried to demarcate computer aided proof. What is remarkable is that the demarcation criteria for computer simulation and computer aided proof are rather similar. As the debate in philosophy of mathematics is more advanced, I will show how its arguments can be translated for the philosophy of computer simulation. I argue that even in the light of computer methods human justificatory capabilities still remain central. In closing I point out, that the focus on justificatory methods like verification/validation in software engineering challenges the traditional philosophical account of engineering.

Keywords

Philosophy of computer simulation Epistemology of computer simulation Philosophy of software engineering 

References

  1. Appel, K., & Haken, W. (1976). Every planar map is four colourable. Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society, 82, 711–712.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Arkoudas, K., & Bringsjord, S. (2007). Computers, justification, and mathematical knowledge. Minds and Machines, 17, 185–202.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Franssen, M., Lokhorst, G.-J., & van de Poel, I. (2015). Philosophy of technology, The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. New York: New York City College of Technology.Google Scholar
  4. Frigg, R., & Reiss, J. (2009). The philosophy of simulation: Hot new issues or same old stew? Synthese, 169, 593–613.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Gabbay, D. M., Meijers, A., & Woods, J. (2009). Philosophy of technology and engineering sciences. Amsterdam: North Holland Elsevier.Google Scholar
  6. Gonthier, G. (2008). Formal proof—The four-color theorem. Notices of the AMS, 55, 1382–1393.Google Scholar
  7. Gruner, S. (2010). Software engineering between technics and science. Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 41, 237–260.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Gruner, S. (2011). Problems for a philosophy of software engineering. Minds and Machines, 21, 275–299.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Grüne-Yanoff, T., & Weirich, P. (2010). The philosophy and epistemology of simulation: A review. Simulation & Gaming, 41, 20–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Humphreys, P. (2009). The philosophical novelty of computer simulation methods. Synthese, 169, 615–626.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. McEvoy, M. (2008). The epistemological status of computer-assisted proofs. Philosophia Mathematica, 16, 374–387.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Popper, K. R. (2005). Gesammelte Werke: Band 3: Logik der Forschung. Tübingen: Mohr-Siebeck.Google Scholar
  13. Teller, P. (1980). Computer proof. The Journal of Philosophy, 77, 797–803.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Tymoczko, T. (1979). The four-color problem and its philosophical significance. The Journal of Philosophy, 76, 57–83.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Tymoczko, T. (1980). Computers, proofs and mathematicians: A philosophical investigation of the four-color proof. Mathematics Magazine, 53, 131–138.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Winsberg, E. (2010). Science in the age of computer simulation. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Zach, R. (2016). Hilbert’s Program, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2016 Edition).Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer International Publishing AG, part of Springer Nature 2018

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.HöchstleistungsrechenzentrumStuttgartGermany

Personalised recommendations