Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Studies in the History of Philosophy of Mind ((SHPM,volume 20))

  • 626 Accesses

Abstract

Although it serves as the ontological and axiological ground for Plato’s political proposal, the tripartite soul theory will remain crippled if we ignore Plato’s criticism of pre-Platonic cultural practices (especially of imitative poetry) and the influence of those cultural practices on the psychological configuration of individuals. With this aspect in mind, this paper has two main objectives: (i) to place Plato’s psychology in the whole context of politics of the soul, with emphasis on the objective sense of this expression (i.e. politics for the soul); and (ii) to emphasize the connection between Plato’s theory of the soul in the Republic and his criticism of imitative poetry in books II, III and X. I will try to show that artistic representation is both a psychological and a political experience: a psycho-political experience which involves metaphysical, epistemological, psychological, and moral dimensions. What is the effect of imitative poetry on human soul? And to what extent does this effect compromise Plato’s psycho-political project?

Sit down in silence, my friend, and be persuaded by my story

Homer, Iliad IV, 412

It seems to me that all deception is a form of sorcery

R. III 413 c

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 109.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    R. IV 434 d ff. For the translation of R. I will use Reeve 2004.

  2. 2.

    R. IV 443c4ff

  3. 3.

    Laks 2007, p. 32. English translations of Laks 2007, Gómez Lobo 1993 and Vegetti 1998 are all mine.

  4. 4.

    R. IX 591 e1–2; cf. X 608b1

  5. 5.

    R. III 413 e3–4.

  6. 6.

    R. IV 443d-444a.

  7. 7.

    Laks 2007, p. 265.

  8. 8.

    ‘A citizen was, in general, a little landowner or artisan who performed military and political functions. The latter consisted in being a jury or taking part in the decisions of the assembly, the state highest authority. In Greece, democracy allowed and demanded to be multifunctional’. See Gómez Lobo , 1993, p. 338.

  9. 9.

    Havelock 1963, p. 12.

  10. 10.

    Grube 1974, pp. 46–47, fn.12; Klosko 2006, pp. 124 ff.

  11. 11.

    R. V 470 b5–470 d; VIII 550 e9-560a. Warlike terminology already appears in Phd. in line with the contrast between body and soul. Bodily appetites cause many wars (πόλεμοι), civil wars (στάσεις) and conflicts (μάχαι) (66 b8-c7).

  12. 12.

    Boeri 2010, p. 292; cf. R. IV 436a.

  13. 13.

    For warlike metaphors and lexicon related to the psychological conflict: R. IV 440e; 442 a-c, Classen 1959, Kühn 1994 and Blössner 1997.

  14. 14.

    Cf. Vegetti 1998, p. 30.

  15. 15.

    R. IV 423 e-424a.

  16. 16.

    Klosko 2006, p. 124.

  17. 17.

    Klosko 2006, pp. 124–125.

  18. 18.

    I use the term ‘art’ in a broad sense in order to include all the artistic representations examined in R.: epic genre, dithyramb, tragedy and also painting, which has an important place in book X.

  19. 19.

    ‘…there is no twofold or manifold man among us (διπλοῦς ἀνὴρ παρ’ ἡμῖν οὐδὲ πολλαπλοῦς)’ (R. 397e).

  20. 20.

    For these aspects, Havelock 1963, especially part I.

  21. 21.

    As Klosko suggests, ‘Plato views the mind as an active probing force, which responds constantly to its environment and is attracted especially to aesthetic creations. Plato is somewhat unusual among political philosophers in the extent to which he believes artistic products affect the soul. Probably no other important political philosopher had as much respect for art, while the political implications are apparent: if art is so powerful, it must be carefully controlled. It is not surprising to see a large portion of the Republic –and a smaller though still significant percentage of the Lg.- given over to regulating the arts ’ (Klosko 2006, p. 125).

  22. 22.

    For the difficulties of relating pictorial art and imitative art in R. X, see Moss 2007 and 2008.

  23. 23.

    This is not the place to treat a topic which is nonetheless very interesting: to what extent is the threefold soul doctrine explicated in book IV coherent with the arguments found in book X? In the latter Plato uses two arguments to show that the soul is divided into two areas: rationality and irrationality. In the first argument (602 c-603 a) he offers the example of optical illusions to distinguish between the soul part which calculates, measures and weighs and the other part which assumes appearances with no criticism. In the second case, the perceptive conflict is replaced by an emotional one: when we face concrete and intense situations, we feel opposite inclinations. One part of our soul leads to an excessive expression of our passions , and the other tends to restrain, contain and moderate such expressions. I take this to be an interesting discussion, which Moss presents 2008 in a convincing way.

  24. 24.

    ‘And the same things appear bent and straight when seen in water or out of it, or concave and convex because sight is misled by colors; and every other similar sort of confusion is clearly present in our soul’ (R. X 602c-603a).

  25. 25.

    ‘And haven’t measuring, counting, and weighing proved to be most welcome assistants in these cases, ensuring that what appears bigger or smaller or more numerous or heavier does not rule within us, but rather what has calculated or measured or even weighed?’ (R. X 603a ff).

  26. 26.

    Moss 2008, p. 35.

  27. 27.

    Plato states that the death of a child belongs to what he calls ‘seeming evils’ (613a, τῶν δοκούντων κακῶν).

  28. 28.

    Achilles is presented as an example of contradictory and excessive behavior when expressing affection (R. III 388a-c).

  29. 29.

    R. X 605b7-c4.

  30. 30.

    R. X 605a9 ff.

  31. 31.

    Nietzsche 2001, pp. 83–4.

  32. 32.

    Ibid. pp. 84–5.

  33. 33.

    R. X 606a-e.

  34. 34.

    Havelock 1963, p. 40.

  35. 35.

    R. II 381a 3–4.

Bibliography

Ancient Texts

  • Plato. Platonis opera. Ed. Burnet, J (Oxford 1900–1907; 1967–1968).

    Google Scholar 

Modern Texts

  • Blößner, N. (1997). Dialogform und Argument: Studien zur Platons Politeia. Akad. d. Wissenschaft u. Liter.-Mainz, Abhandl.d. Geistes-u.Sozialwiss. Klasse 1.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boeri, M. (2010). ¿Por qué el θυμός es un aliado de la razón en la batalla contra los apetitos irracionales? Rivista de cultura classia e medioevale, 52(2), 289–306.

    Google Scholar 

  • Classen, C. J. (1959). Sprachliche Deutung als Triebkraft platonischen und sokratischen Philosophie. Zetemata XII.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gómez Lobo, A. (1993). Escritos Políticos de Platón. Estudios Públicos, 51, 337–410.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grube, G. M. A. (1974). Plato: The republic. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Havelock, E. A. (1963). Preface to Plato. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klosko, G. (2006). The development of Plato’s political theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kühn, W. (1994). Caractéres collectifs et individuels. Platon, République IV, 434 d2-436b3. Revue de philosophie ancienne, 12(1), 45–64.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laks, A. (2007). La filosofía política de Platón a la luz de las Leyes. Ediciones de la Universidad Autónoma de México.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moss, J. (2007). What is imitative poetry and why is it bad? In G. R. F. Ferrari (Ed.), The Cambridge companion to Plato’s republic (pp. 415–444). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Moss, J. (2008). Appearances and calculations: Plato’s division of the soul. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 34, 35–68.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, F. (2001). The gay science. In B. Williams (Ed.)., and translated by J. Nauckhof. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reeve, C. D. C. (2004). Republic., translated from the New standard Greek text, with introduction, C. D. C. Reeve. Indianapolis/Cambridge: Hackett Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vegetti, M. (1998). La Reppublica (vol. III). Bibliopolis.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Iván de los Ríos .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer International Publishing AG, part of Springer Nature

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

de los Ríos, I. (2018). Politics of the Soul in Plato’s Republic . In: Boeri, M.D., Kanayama, Y.Y., Mittelmann, J. (eds) Soul and Mind in Greek Thought. Psychological Issues in Plato and Aristotle. Studies in the History of Philosophy of Mind, vol 20. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-78547-9_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics