Skip to main content

Online Processing of “Real” and “Fake”: The Cost of Being Too Strong

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Semantics of Gradability, Vagueness, and Scale Structure

Part of the book series: Language, Cognition, and Mind ((LCAM,volume 4))

Abstract

Strengthening literal meanings of linguistic expressions appears central to communicative success. Weakening on the other hand would appear not to be viable given that literal meaning already grossly underdetermines reality, let alone possibility. We discuss productive weakening in fake-type adjectival modification and present evidence from event-related brain potentials that such weakening has neurophysiological consequences and is qualitatively different from other mechanisms of modification. Specifically, the processing of fake-type constructions (e.g., “a fake diamond”) evokes a Late Positivity as characteristic of certain types of referential shift or reconceptualization. We argue that fake-type composition involves an intermediate representation that is semantically contradictory and that the Late Positivity reflects an interface repair mechanism that redresses the contradiction. In contrast, composition involving reputedly over-informative real-type adjectives evokes no comparable processing costs.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
EUR 32.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or Ebook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 79.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    In the literature, the term privative is often used for what we call fake-type adjectives here. As we believe the case to be more general (viz., “constructional” in the case of e.g. animal-for-statue alternations, cf. below) and as we do not intend to engage in the discussion of adjective classification (cf. Kamp and Partee 1995; Morzycki 2015), we stick to the neutral term in what follows. Lakoff and Johnson (1980:120f) propose that privative adjectives like fake do negate purposive and functional properties (as opposed to perceptual and motor activity properties) as making up the multidimensional Gestalt associated with fake-modified nominals. Partee (2010) on the other hand gives an argument based on Polish NP split phenomena that fake-type adjectives that can occur in predicative position should be regarded as subsective adjectives additionally entailing coercion to the effect of loosening the overall interpretation.

  2. 2.

    Peirce (MS 678:34, 1910) states: “…that which characterizes and defines an assertion of possibility is its emancipation from the Principle of Contradiction”.

  3. 3.

    Contradictions are the strongest possible meanings as they exclude everything. Brandt (2016) argues that the hidden aspectual-temporal, modal or comparative meaning of inchoative, middle, excessive and directional complement constructions should be regarded as the result of the same interface repair mechanism that circumvents a violation of the law of contradiction by introducing an extra quantification (or rather by semantically dislocating a problematic meaning component).

  4. 4.

    Note that nothing excludes that weakening and strengthening apply with respect to one and the same construction. For the cases at hand at least, weakening should apply first (as it makes no sense to strengthen contradictory statements).

  5. 5.

    Question-answer sequences were adopted in this study which was conducted in German verb-final constructions to assure that the mismatch between the predicate and the noun was measurable at the noun. Accordingly, the question introduced the predicate and generated a high expectation for a content-denoting expression, thereby creating a semantic type conflict as early as at the point of encountering the noun in the answer.

  6. 6.

    Note that for reasons of space, we did not include the separate analysis for the midline electrodes, which registered comparable results.

References

  • Austin, J. L. (1962). Sense and sensibilia. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baggio, G., Choma, T., van Lambalgen, M., & Hagoort, P. (2010). Coercion and compositionality. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 22(9), 2131–2140.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brandt, P. (2016). Fehlkonstruktion und Reparatur in der Bedeutungskomposition. Linguistische Berichte, 248, 395–433.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carston, R. (1997). Enrichment and loosening: Complementary processes in deriving the proposition expressed. Linguistische Berichte, 8, 103–127.

    Google Scholar 

  • Engelhardt, P. E., Demiral, B., & Ferreira, F. (2011). Over-specified referring expressions impair comprehension: An ERP study. Brain and Cognition, 77(2), 304–314.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Franks, B. (1995). Sense generation: A “quasi-classical” approach to concepts and concept combination. Cognitive Science, 19, 441–505.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frisson, S. (2009). Semantic underspecification in language processing. Language and Linguistics Compass, 3(1), 111–127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frisson, S., Pickering, M. J., & McElree, B. (2011). The difficult mountain: Enriched composition in adjective-noun phrases. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 18(6), 1172–1179.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grice, H. P. (1989). Studies in the way of words. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, H. P. (1975). Logic and conversation. In P. Cole & J. L. Morgan (Eds.), Speech acts (pp. 41–58). New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hampton, J. A. (1987). Inheritance of attributes in natural concept conjunctions. Memory and Cognition, 15, 55–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heim, I. (2008). Decomposing antonyms. Proceedings of Sinn und Bedeutung, 12, 212–225.

    Google Scholar 

  • Herbert, C., Junghofer, M., & Kissler, J. (2008). Event related potentials to emotional adjectives during reading. Psychophysiology, 45(3), 487–498.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horn, L. R. (1984). Toward a new taxonomy for pragmatic inference: Q-based and R-based implicature in context. In D. Schiffrin (Ed.), Meaning, form and use in context: Linguistic applications (pp. 11–42). Washington: Georgetown University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kamp, H., & Partee, B. (1995). Prototype theory and compositionality. Cognition, 57(2), 129–191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kennedy, C. (2001). Polar opposition and the ontology of ‘degrees’. Linguistics and Philosophy, 24(1), 33–70.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kutas, M., & Federmeier, K. D. (2011). Thirty years and counting: Finding meaning in the N400 component of the event-related brain potential (ERP). Annual Review of Psychology, 62, 621–647.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff, G., & Johnson, M. (1980). Metaphors we live by. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lawrence, M. A. (2013). ez: Easy Analysis and Visualization of Factorial Experiments. R Package Version 4.2-2. http://CRAN.R-project.org/package=ez.

  • McElree, B., Frisson, S., & Pickering, M. J. (2006). Deferred interpretations: Why starting Dickens is taxing but reading Dickens isn’t. Cognitive Science, 30(1), 181–192.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morzycki, M. (2015). Modification. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nunberg, G. (1979). The non-uniqueness of semantic solutions: Polysemy. Linguistics and Philosophy, 3(2), 143–184.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Partee, B. (2010). Privative adjectives: Subsective plus coercion. In R. Bäuerle, U. Reyle, & T. E. Zimmermann (Eds.), Presuppositions and discourse (pp. 273–285). Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C. S. (1910). The Charles S. Peirce papers (Microfilm ed.). Cambridge: Harvard University.

    Google Scholar 

  • R Core Team. (2015). R: A language and environment for statistical computing. Vienna: R Foundation for Statistical Computing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1940). An inquiry into meaning and truth. London: Allen & Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sassoon, G. W. (2013). A typology of multidimensional adjectives. Journal of Semantics, 30(3), 335–380.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sauerland, U., & Schumacher, P. B. (2016). Pragmatics: Theory and experiment growing together. Linguistische Berichte, 245, 3–24.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schumacher, P. B. (2014). Content and context in incremental processing: “The ham sandwich” revisited. Philosophical Studies, 168(1), 151–165.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schumacher, P. B. (2013). When combinatorial processing results in reconceptualization: Towards a new approach of compositionality. Frontiers in Psychology, 4(677).

    Google Scholar 

  • Traxler, M. J., Pickering, M. J., & McElree, B. (2002). Coercion in sentence processing: Evidence from eye-movements and self-paced reading. Journal of Memory and Language, 47(4), 530–547.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weiland-Breckle, H., & Schumacher, P. B. (2017). Artist-for-work metonymy: Type clash or underspecification? Mental Lexicon, 12(2), 219–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We would like to thank Claudia Kilter, Fabienne Bartsch, Filiz Özden and Johanna Kasper for their assistance during data collection. This research was supported by the DFG-funded XPrag.de project of the first author (SCHU 2517/6-1).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Petra B. Schumacher .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer International Publishing AG, part of Springer Nature

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Schumacher, P.B., Brandt, P., Weiland-Breckle, H. (2018). Online Processing of “Real” and “Fake”: The Cost of Being Too Strong. In: Castroviejo, E., McNally, L., Weidman Sassoon, G. (eds) The Semantics of Gradability, Vagueness, and Scale Structure. Language, Cognition, and Mind, vol 4. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-77791-7_4

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-77791-7_4

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-77790-0

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-77791-7

  • eBook Packages: Social SciencesSocial Sciences (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics