Skip to main content

Epistemic Logic and Epistemology

  • Chapter
  • First Online:

Part of the book series: Springer Undergraduate Texts in Philosophy ((SUTP))

Abstract

This chapter provides a brief introduction to propositional epistemic logic and its applications to epistemology. No previous exposure to epistemic logic is assumed. Epistemic-logical topics discussed include the language and semantics of basic epistemic logic, multi-agent epistemic logic, combined epistemic-doxastic logic, and a glimpse of dynamic epistemic logic. Epistemological topics discussed include Moore-paradoxical phenomena, the surprise exam paradox, logical omniscience and epistemic closure, formalized theories of knowledge, debates about higher-order knowledge, and issues of knowability raised by Fitch’s paradox. The references and recommended readings provide gateways for further exploration.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   69.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   89.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    To reduce clutter, I will not put quote marks around symbols and sentences of the formal language, trusting that no confusion will arise.

  2. 2.

    In our formal models, “scenarios” will be unstructured points at which atomic sentences can be true or false. We are not committed to thinking of them as Lewisian possible worlds.

  3. 3.

    Hintikka presented his original formal framework somewhat differently. Such details aside, we use the now standard relational structure semantics for normal modal logics.

  4. 4.

    It is important to draw a distinction between epistemic accessibility and other notions of indistinguishability. Suppose that we replace R K by a binary relation E on W, where our intuitive interpretation is that wEv holds “iff the subject’s perceptual experience and memory” in scenario v “exactly match his perceptual experience and memory” in scenario w [28, 553]. Suppose we were to then define the truth of in w as in (MC), but with R K replaced by E. In other words, the agent knows φ in w iff φ is true in all scenarios that are experientially indistinguishable from w for the agent. (Of course, we could just as well reinterpret R K in this way, without the new E notation.) There are two conceptual differences between the picture with E and the one with R K. First, given the version of (MC) with E, the epistemic model with E does not simply represent the content of one’s knowledge; rather, it commits us to a particular view of the conditions under which an agent has knowledge, specified in terms of perceptual experience and memory. Second, given our interpretation of E, it is plausible that E has certain properties, such as symmetry (wEv iff vEw), which are questionable as properties of R K (see Sect. 17.7). Since the properties of the relation determine the valid principles for the knowledge operator K (as explained in Sects. 17.3 and 17.7), we must be clear about which interpretation of the relation we adopt: epistemic accessibility, experiential indistinguishability, or something else. Here we adopt the accessibility interpretation.

    Finally, note that while one may read wR K v as “for all the agent knows in w, scenario v might be the scenario he is in,” one should not read wR K v as “in w, the agent considers scenario v possible,” where the latter suggest a subjective psychological notion. The spymaster may not subjectively consider it possible that his spy, whom he has regarded for years as his most trusted agent, has defected. It obviously does not follow that he knows that his spy has not defected, as it would according to the subjective reading of R K together with (MC).

  5. 5.

    For any theory of knowledge that can be stated in terms of R K and (MC), the rule RK of Sect. 17.3 must be sound. Therefore, theories for which RK is not sound, such as those discussed in Sect. 17.6, cannot be stated in this way. Given a formalization of such a theory, one can always define a relation R K on scenarios such that wR K v holds iff everything the agent knows in w according to the formalization is true in v. It is immediate from this definition that if φ is not true in some v such that wR K v, then the agent does not know φ in w. However, it is not immediate that if φ is true in all v such that wR K v, then the agent knows φ in w. It is the right-to-left direction of (MC) that is not neutral with respect to all theories of knowledge.

  6. 6.

    Throughout we use the nomenclature of modal logic for schemas and rules.

  7. 7.

    For additional ways of understanding idealization in epistemic logic, see [45].

  8. 8.

    A similar formalization applies to the designated student paradox [33, 317], a genuinely multi-agent version of the surprise exam paradox.

  9. 9.

    We skip steps for the sake of space. E.g., we obtain (4) by applying RK 2 to the tautology ((e 1 ∨ e 2) ∧¬e 1) → e 2. We then obtain (5) directly from (4) using the special case of RK 1 where n = 0 in the premise (φ 1 ∧⋯ ∧ φ n) → ψ, known as Necessitation: if ψ is a theorem, so is K 1 ψ. It is important to remember that RK i can only be applied to theorems of the logic, not to sentences that we have derived using undischarged assumptions like (A), (B), and (C). To be careful, we should keep track of the undischarged assumptions at each point in the derivation, but this is left to the reader as an exercise. Clearly we have not derived (8) as a theorem of the logic, since the assumptions (A), (B), and (C) are still undischarged. What we have derived as a theorem of the logic is the sentence abbreviated by ((A) ∧ (B) ∧ (C)) → (8).

  10. 10.

    We can derive (8) from (A), (B), and (C) in a doxastic logic (see Sect. 17.5) without the T axiom, substituting B i for K i. Thus, insofar as B 1(e 1 ∧¬B 1 e 1) is also problematic for an ideal agent, the surprise exam paradox poses a problem about belief as well as knowledge.

  11. 11.

    In fact, the sentence ¬B(p ∧¬Bp) precisely corresponds to a condition on R B, namely that for every w, there is a v such that wR B v and for every u, vR B u implies wR B u.

  12. 12.

    Note that the K axiom is derivable from the RK rule with the tautology (φ ∧ (φ → ψ)) → ψ.

  13. 13.

    Assume ¬φ is true in w, so φ is not true in w. Consider some v with wR K v. By symmetry, vR K w. Then since φ is not true in w, is not true in v by (MC), so ¬ is true in v. Since v was arbitrary, ¬ is true in all v such that wR K v, so K¬ is true in w by (MC).

  14. 14.

    Note that if we reject the requirement that R K be symmetric in every epistemic model, we can still allow models in which R K is symmetric (such as the model in Fig. 17.1), when this is appropriate to model an agent’s knowledge. The same applies for other properties.

  15. 15.

    Assuming  → , D, and 5, the principle BKφ →  is derivable (see [16, §2.4]). Given the same assumptions, if an agent is a “stickler” [30, 246] who believes something only if she believes that she knows it ( → BKφ), then one can even derive  ↔  (see [26] and [17]). Given  → , D, B, and  → BKφ, one can still derive  → φ (see [17, 485]).

  16. 16.

    To see that 4 is valid over the class of transitive models, assume that is true in w in such a model, so by (MC), φ is true in all v such that wR K v. Consider some u with wR K u. Toward proving that is true in u, consider some v with uR K v. By transitivity, wR K u and uR K v implies wR K v. Hence by our initial assumption, φ is true in v. Since v was arbitrary, φ is true in all v such that uR K v, so is true in u by (MC). Finally, since u was arbitrary, is true in all u such that wR K u, so KKφ is true in w by (MC).

  17. 17.

    Assuming D, 4, and M for B, we have: (i) B(p ∧¬Bp), assumption for reductio; (ii) Bp ∧ B¬Bp, from (i) by M for B and PL; (iii) BBp ∧ B¬Bp, from (ii) by 4 for B and PL; (iv) ¬B¬Bp ∧ B¬Bp, from (iii) by D and PL; (v) ¬B(p ∧¬Bp), from (i)-(iv) by PL.

  18. 18.

    Stalnaker shows that the epistemic logic of the defeasibility analysis as formalized is S4.3, which is intermediate in strength between Lenzen’s lower and upper bounds of S4.2 and S4.4.

  19. 19.

    Note that the universal quantifiers in (9), (10), (15), and (21) are not part of our formal language. They are merely shorthand to indicate a schema of sentences.

  20. 20.

    For discussion of such “unsuccessful” announcements in the context of the surprise exam paradox, see [15].

  21. 21.

    See [22, Ch. 6], [16, §5], and [1] for discussion of quantified epistemic logic. Hintikka [23] has proposed a “second generation” epistemic logic, based on independence-friendly first-order logic, aimed at solving the difficulties and fulfilling the epistemological promises of quantified epistemic logic.

  22. 22.

    For helpful discussion and comments, I wish to thank Johan van Benthem, Tomohiro Hoshi, Thomas Icard, Alex Kocurek, Eric Pacuit, John Perry, Igor Sedlár, Justin Vlasits, and the students in my Fall 2012 seminar on Epistemic Logic and Epistemology at UC Berkeley.

References and Recommended Readings

  1. Aloni, M. (2005). Individual concepts in modal predicate logic. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 34(1), 1–64. *** For a modern treatment of classic puzzles of quantified epistemic logic, go here next.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Artemov, S. (2008). The logic of justification. The Review of Symbolic Logic, 1(4), 477–513

    Article  Google Scholar 

  3. Balbiani, P., Baltag, A., van Ditmarsch, H., Herzig, A., Hoshi, T., & de Lima, T. (2008). ‘Knowable’ as ‘Known after an Announcement’. The Review of Symbolic Logic, 1, 305–334.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. Baltag, A., & Smets, S. (2008). A qualitative theory of dynamic belief revision. In G. Bonanno, W. van der Hoek, & M. Wooldridge (Eds.), Logic and the foundations of game and decision theory (Texts in logic and games, Vol. 3, pp. 13–60). Amsterdam: Amsterdam University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  5. van Benthem, J. (2004). What one may come to know. Analysis, 64(2), 95–105. ***For further philosophical introduction to dynamic epistemic logic, go here next. A longer version appears as Chapter 9 of [32].

    Article  Google Scholar 

  6. van Benthem, J. (2006). Epistemic logic and epistemology: The state of their affairs. Philosophical Studies, 128(1), 49–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. van Benthem, J. (2011). Logical dynamics of information and interaction. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  8. Board, O. (2004). Dynamic interactive epistemology. Games and Economic Behavior, 49, 49–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  9. Bonnay, D., & Egré, P. (2009). Inexact knowledge with introspection. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 38, 179–227.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. van Ditmarsch, H., van der Hoek, W., & Iliev, P. (2011). Everything is knowable – how to get to know whether a proposition is true. Theoria, 78(2), 93–114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. Dretske, F. (1970). Epistemic operators. The Journal of Philosophy, 67(24), 1007–1023. ***A classic source of current debates about epistemic closure.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Edgington, D. (1985). The paradox of knowability. Mind, 94(376), 557–568.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. Ègre, P. (2011). Epistemic logic. In L. Horsten & R. Pettigrew (Eds.), The continuum companion to philosophical logic (Continuum companions, pp. 503–542). New York: Continuum. ***For an introduction to further topics in epistemic logic, go here next.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Fitch, F. B. (1963). A logical analysis of some value concepts. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 28(2), 135–142.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  15. Gerbrandy, J. (2007). The surprise examination in dynamic epistemic logic. Synthese, 155, 21–33.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  16. Gochet, P., & Gribomont, P. (2006). Epistemic logic. In D. M. Gabbay & J. Woods (Eds.), Handbook of the history of logic (Vol. 7). Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Halpern, J. Y. (1996). Should knowledge entail belief? Journal of Philosophical Logic, 25, 483–494.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. Halpern, J. Y., & Pucella, R. (2011). Dealing with logical omniscience: Expressiveness and pragmatics. Artificial Intelligence, 175, 220–235.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  19. Hendricks, V. F. (2005). Mainstream and formal epistemology. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  20. Hendricks, V. F., & Pritchard, D. (Eds.). (2008). Epistemology: 5 questions. Copenhagen: Automatic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Hendricks, V. F., & Roy, O. (Eds.). (2010). Epistemic logic: 5 questions. Copenhagen: Automatic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Hintikka, J. (1962). Knowledge and belief: An introduction to the logic of the two notions. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. ***The founding text of modern epistemic logic, still worth reading.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Hintikka, J. (2003). A second generation epistemic logic and its general significance. In V. F. Hendricks, K. F. Jørgensen, & S. A. Pedersen (Eds.), Knowledge contributors (Synthese library, Vol. 322). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  24. Holliday, W. H. (2015). Epistemic closure and epistemic logic I: Relevant alternatives and subjunctivism. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 44(1), 1–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  25. Holliday, W. H. (2017). Knowledge, time, and paradox: Introducing sequential epistemic logic. In H. van Ditmarsch & G. Sandu (Eds.), Jaakko Hintikka on knowledge and game theoretical semantics (Outstanding contributions to logic, Vol. 12). New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Lenzen, W. (1978). Recent work in epistemic logic. Acta Philosophica Fennica, 30, 1–219.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Lewis, D. (1986). On the plurality of worlds. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Lewis, D. (1996). Elusive knowledge. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 74(4), 549–567.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  29. Moore, G. E. (1942). A reply to my critics. In P. A. Schilpp (Ed.), The philosophy of G.E. Moore (pp. 535–677). Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Nozick, R. (1981). Philosophical explanations. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Pacuit, E. (2013). Dynamic epistemic logic I and II. Philosophy Compass, 8(9), 798–833.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  32. Salerno, J. (Ed.). (2009). New essays on the knowability paradox. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Sorensen, R. (1988). Blindspots. Oxford: Clarendon Press. ***Filled with fascinating material relevant to epistemic logic.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Sorensen, R. (2002). Formal problems about knowledge. In P. K. Moser (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of epistemology (pp. 539–595). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  35. Sorensen, R, “Epistemic Paradoxes”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2017 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2017/entries/epistemic-paradoxes/.

  36. Stalnaker, R. (1996). Knowledge, belief and counterfactual reasoning in games. Economics and Philosophy, 12, 133–162.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  37. Stalnaker, R. (2006). On logics of knowledge and belief. Philosophical Studies, 128(1), 169–199. ***For more on the interaction of knowledge and belief, go here next.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  38. Stine, G. C. (1976). Skepticism, relevant alternatives, and deductive closure. Philosophical Studies, 29(4), 249–261.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  39. Vanderschraaf, Peter and Sillari, Giacomo, “Common Knowledge”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2014 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/common-knowledge/.

  40. Williamson, T. (1999). Rational failures of the KK principle. In C. Bicchieri, R. C. Jeffrey, & B. Skyrms (Eds.), The logic of strategy (pp. 101–118). New York: Oxford University Press. ***For payoffs of applying epistemic logic to epistemology, start here or with one of Williamson’s other papers.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its limits. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Williamson, T. (2013). Gettier cases in epistemic logic. Inquiry, 56(1), 1–14.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  43. Williamson, T. (2014). Very improbable knowing. Erkenntnis, 79(5), 971–999.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  44. Williamson, T. (2015). A note on Gettier cases in epistemic logic. Philosophical Studies, 172(1), 129–140.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  45. Yap, A. (2014). Idealization, epistemic logic, and epistemology. Synthese, 191(14), 3351–3366.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Wesley H. Holliday .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer International Publishing AG, part of Springer Nature

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Holliday, W.H. (2018). Epistemic Logic and Epistemology. In: Hansson, S., Hendricks, V. (eds) Introduction to Formal Philosophy. Springer Undergraduate Texts in Philosophy. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-77434-3_17

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics