Advertisement

Seeing Things as They Are

  • Marc Champagne
Chapter
Part of the Studies in the History of Philosophy of Mind book series (SHPM, volume 19)

Abstract

In the previous chapter, I added similarity-based signs or icons to the standard menu of referential options. In this chapter, I want to explore the ramifications of this addition for perception. Peirce saw good reason to push his prescissive analysis of iconicity down to a single quality. I thus contrast his account with that of John Poinsot, a medieval philosopher who held that a sign always retains a slight distinction between the object it signifies and the vehicle that does the signifying. Because iconic merger gives us a way to vindicate ordinary perception, I favour Peirce’s stance. The resulting view goes against the claim, put forward by John Locke, that the “secondary” qualities we experience are mere figments. I therefore do my best to undermine that Lockean worldview. Although some philosophers believe that putting qualities back into the world results in panpsychism, I try to find a less far-fetched way to express this.

References

  1. Aho T (2014) Sense perception: early modern theories. In: Knuuttila S, Sihvola J (eds) Sourcebook for the history of the philosophy of mind: philosophical psychology from Plato to Kant, Studies in the history of philosophy of mind, vol 12. Springer, Dordrecht, pp 81–104CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Albertazzi L (2012) Qualitative perceiving. J Conscious Stud 19(11–12):6–31Google Scholar
  3. Allen K (2016) A naïve realist theory of colour. Oxford University Press, OxfordCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Aristotle (1993) De anima (trans: Hamlyn DW). Clarendon, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  5. Armstrong DM (1999) The mind-body problem: an opinionated introduction. Westview Press, BoulderGoogle Scholar
  6. Balibar E (2013) Identity and difference: John Locke and the invention of consciousness (trans: Montag W). Verso, LondonGoogle Scholar
  7. Bayne T (2004) Closing the gap? Some questions for neurophenomenology. Phenomenol Cogn Sci 3(4):349–364CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Beuchot M, Deely JN (1995) Common sources for the semiotic of Charles Peirce and John Poinsot. Rev Metaphys 48(3):539–566Google Scholar
  9. Boler JF (2004) Peirce and medieval thought. In: Misak C (ed) The Cambridge companion to Peirce. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 58–86CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Byrne A, Hilbert D (2003) Color realism and color science. Behav Brain Sci 26(1):3–21Google Scholar
  11. Carruthers P (2000) Phenomenal consciousness: a naturalistic theory. Cambridge University Press, CambridgeCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Chalmers DJ (2015) Panpsychism and panprotopsychism. In: Alter T, Nagasawa Y (eds) Consciousness in the physical world: essays on Russellian monism. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 246–276Google Scholar
  13. Champagne M (2015) Disjunctivism and the ethics of disbelief. Philos Pap 44(2):139–163CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Churchland PM (1996) The engine of reason, the seat of the soul: a philosophical journey into the brain. MIT Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  15. Colapietro VM (2010) Peirce today. Pragmatism Today 1(2):7–24Google Scholar
  16. Crane T, Mellor DH (1990) There is no question of physicalism. Mind 99(394):185–206CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Dalcourt GJ (1994) Poinsot and the mental imagery debate. Mod Sch 72(1):1–12CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Davidson DH (2001) Subjective, intersubjective, objective. Clarendon Press, OxfordCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Deacon TW (2011) Incomplete nature: how mind emerged from matter. W. W. Norton, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  20. Deely JN (1982) Antecedents to Peirce’s notion of iconic signs. In: Lenhart MD, Herzfeld M (eds) Semiotics 1980. Plenum, New York, pp 109–120CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Deely JN (1990) Basics of semiotics. Indiana University Press, BloomingtonGoogle Scholar
  22. Deely JN (1994) Locke’s philosophy versus Locke’s proposal for semiotic. Am J Semiot 11(3–4):33–37Google Scholar
  23. Deely JN (2001) Four ages of understanding. University of Toronto Press, TorontoCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Deely JN (2003) The word “semiotics”: formation and origins. Semiotica 146(1–4):1–49CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Deely JN (2009) Basics of semiotics, 5th edn. Tartu University Press, TartuGoogle Scholar
  26. Dodd J (1995) McDowell and identity theories of truth. Analysis 55(3):160–165CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Fodor JA (1983) The modularity of mind: an essay on faculty psychology. MIT Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  28. Furton EJ (1995) A medieval semiotic: reference and representation in John of St. Thomas’ theory of signs. Peter Lang, BernGoogle Scholar
  29. Furton EJ (1997) The constitution of the object in Immanuel Kant and John Poinsot. Rev Metaphys 51(1):55–75Google Scholar
  30. Goodman N (1976) Languages of art: an approach to a theory of symbols. Hackett, IndianapolisGoogle Scholar
  31. Harman G (1990) The intrinsic quality of experience. In: Tomberlin JE (ed) Philosophical perspectives, vol 4. Ridgeview, Atascadero, pp 31–52Google Scholar
  32. Harnad S (2002) Symbol grounding and the origin of language. In: Scheutz M (ed) Computationalism: new directions. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 143–158Google Scholar
  33. Hilbert D (1987) Color and color perception: a study in anthropomorphic realism. Center for the Study of Language and Information, StanfordGoogle Scholar
  34. Hookway C (2007) Peirce on icons and cognition. In: Priss U, Polovina S, Hill R (eds) Conceptual structures: knowledge architectures for smart applications. Springer, Berlin, pp 59–68CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Huxley TH (1866) Lessons in elementary physiology. MacMillan, LondonGoogle Scholar
  36. Jackson F (1982) Epiphenomenal qualia. Philos Q 32(127):127–136CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Jackson F (1986) What Mary didn’t know. J Philos 83(5):291–295CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Jackson F (2004) Postscript on qualia. In: Ludlow P, Nagasawa Y, Stoljar D (eds) There’s something about Mary: essays on phenomenal consciousness and Frank Jackson’s knowledge argument. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 417–420Google Scholar
  39. Jacovides M (1999) Locke’s resemblance theses. The Philosophical Review 108(4):461–496CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Jacovides M (2007) Locke’s distinctions between primary and secondary qualities. In: Newman L (ed) The Cambridge companion to Locke’s “Essay concerning human understanding”. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 101–129Google Scholar
  41. James W (1975) The meaning of truth. Longmans, Green, and Company, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  42. James W (2007) The principles of psychology, vol 2. Cosimo, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  43. Johnston M (1992) How to speak of the colours. Philos Stud 68(3):221–263CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. Kelley D (1988) The evidence of the senses: a realist theory of perception. Louisiana State University Press, Baton RougeGoogle Scholar
  45. King P (1994) Scholasticism and the philosophy of mind: the failure of Aristotelian psychology. In: Horowitz T, Janis AI (eds) Scientific failure. Rowman and Littlefield, Lanham, pp 109–138Google Scholar
  46. Kirkham RL (1997) Theories of truth: a critical introduction. MIT Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  47. Ladyman J, Ross D, Spurrett D, Collier J (2007) Every thing must go: metaphysics naturalized. Oxford University Press, OxfordCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  48. Legg C (2013) What is a logical diagram? In: Moktefi A, Shin S-J (eds) Visual reasoning with diagrams. Birkhäuser, Heidelberg, pp 1–18Google Scholar
  49. Levine J (2007) Phenomenal concepts and the materialist constraint. In: Alter T, Walter S (eds) Phenomenal concepts and phenomenal knowledge: new essays on consciousness and physicalism. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 145–166CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  50. Lewtas P (2013) What it is like to be a quark. J Conscious Stud 20(9–10):39–64Google Scholar
  51. Livingston PM (2004) Philosophical history and the problem of consciousness. Cambridge University Press, CambridgeCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  52. Locke J (1825) An essay concerning human understanding. Thomas Davison, LondonGoogle Scholar
  53. MacFarlane J (2014) Assessment sensitivity: relative truth and its applications. Oxford University Press, OxfordCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  54. Marmo C (1987) The semiotics of John Poinsot. Versus 46:109–129Google Scholar
  55. Maroosis J (2003) Poinsot, Peirce, and Pegis: knowing as a way of being. In: Redpath PA (ed) A Thomistic tapestry. Rodopi, Amsterdam, pp 157–176Google Scholar
  56. McDowell J (1996) Mind and world. Harvard University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  57. McGinn C (1989) Can we solve the mind-body problem? Mind 98(891):349–366CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  58. Murphy JB (1994) Language, communication, and representation in the semiotic of John Poinsot. Thomist 58(4):569–598CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  59. Nagel T (2012) Mind and cosmos: why the materialist neo-Darwinian conception of nature is almost certainly false. Oxford University Press, OxfordCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  60. O’Dea J (2002) The indexical nature of sensory concepts. Philos Pap 31(2):169–181CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  61. Papineau D (2003) Theories of consciousness. In: Smith Q, Jokic A (eds) Consciousness: new philosophical perspectives. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 353–383Google Scholar
  62. Papineau D (2006) Comments on Galen Strawson. In: Strawson G, Freeman A (eds) Consciousness and its place in nature: does physicalism entail panpsychism? Imprint Academic, Exeter, pp 100–109Google Scholar
  63. Papineau D (2007) Phenomenal and perceptual concepts. In: Alter T, Walter S (eds) Phenomenal concepts and phenomenal knowledge: new essays on consciousness and physicalism. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 111–144Google Scholar
  64. Peirce CS ( 1931–58) The collected papers of Charles Sanders Peirce. Harvard University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  65. Peirce CS (1998) The essential Peirce: selected philosophical writings, vol 2. Indiana University Press, BloomingtonGoogle Scholar
  66. Peirce CS (2015a) Division of signs. Sign Syst Stud 43(4):651–662Google Scholar
  67. Peirce CS (2015b) Two papers on existential graphs by Charles Peirce. Synthese 192(4):881–922CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  68. Pellerey R (1989) Thomas Aquinas: natural semiotics and the epistemological process. In: Eco U, Marmo C (eds) On the medieval theory of signs. John Benjamins, Amsterdam, pp 81–105Google Scholar
  69. Poinsot J (2013) Tractatus de signis: the semiotic of John Poinsot (trans: Deely JN, Powell RA). St. Augustine’s Press, South BendGoogle Scholar
  70. Potrč M (2008) The world of qualia. In: Wright E (ed) The case for qualia. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 109–124CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  71. Prinz JJ (2002) Furnishing the mind: concepts and their perceptual basis. MIT Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  72. Pylyshyn ZW (1984) Computation and cognition: toward a foundation for cognitive science. MIT Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  73. Quine WVO (1966) The ways of paradox and other essays. Random House, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  74. Ransdell JM (1978) A misunderstanding of Peirce’s phenomenology. Philos Phenomenol Res 38(4):550–553CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  75. Ransdell JM (1979) The epistemic function of iconicity in perception. In: Ketner KL, Ransdell JM (eds) Studies in Peirce’s semiotic. Institute for studies in pragmaticism, Lubbock, pp 51–66Google Scholar
  76. Ransdell JM (2003) Iconicity revisited. Semio Inq 23(1–3):221–240Google Scholar
  77. Rasmussen DB (1994) The significance for cognitive realism of the thought of John Poinsot. American Catholic Philos Q 68(3):409–424Google Scholar
  78. Rosenthal DM (2010) How to think about mental qualities. Philosophical Issues 20:368–393CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  79. Runes DD (ed) (1980) Dictionary of philosophy: ancient, medieval, modern. Littlefield, TotowaGoogle Scholar
  80. Russell B (2015) My philosophical development. In: Alter T, Nagasawa Y (eds) Consciousness in the physical world: essays on Russellian monism. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 46–57Google Scholar
  81. Santaella L (2003) Why there is no crisis of representation, according to Peirce. Semiotica 143(1–4):45–52Google Scholar
  82. Searle JR (1980) Minds, brains, and programs. Behav Brain Sci 3(3):417–424CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  83. Sebeok TA, Danesi M (2000) The forms of meaning: modeling systems theory and semiotic analysis. Mouton de Gruyter, BerlinCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  84. Sellars W (1991) Science, perception and reality. Ridgeview, AtascaderoGoogle Scholar
  85. Shoemaker S (1994) Self-knowledge and inner-sense; lecture III: the phenomenal character of experience. Philos Phenomenol Res 54(2):291–314CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  86. Strawson G (2006) Consciousness and its place in nature: does physicalism entail panpsychism? Imprint Academic, ExeterGoogle Scholar
  87. Stroud-Drinkwater C (1994) The naive theory of colour. Philos Phenomenol Res 54(2):345–354CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  88. Sundström P (2007) Colour and consciousness: untying the metaphysical knot. Philos Stud 136(2):123–165CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  89. Tiercelin C (2006) The importance of the medievals in the constitution of Peirce’s semeiotic and thought-sign theory. In: Fabbrichesi R, Marietti S (eds) Semiotics and philosophy in Charles Sanders Peirce. Cambridge Scholars, Newcastle upon Tyne, pp 158–184Google Scholar
  90. Tootell RBH, Silverman MS, Switkes E, Valois RLD (1982) Deoxyglucose analysis of retinotopic organization in primate striate cortex. Science 218(4575):902–904CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  91. Tye M (1995) Ten problems of consciousness: a representational theory of the phenomenal mind. MIT Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  92. Tye M (2000) Consciousness, color, and content. MIT Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  93. Violi P (2007) Semiosis without consciousness? An ontogenetic perspective. Cogn Semiot 1:65–88Google Scholar
  94. Weinberg S (2016) Consciousness in Locke. Oxford University Press, OxfordCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  95. Wild J (1947) An introduction to the phenomenology of signs. Philos Phenomenol Res 8(2):217–233CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  96. Wittgenstein L (2002) Tractatus logico-philosophicus (trans: Ogden CK, Ramsey FP). Routledge, LondonGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer International Publishing AG 2018

Authors and Affiliations

  • Marc Champagne
    • 1
  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyTrent UniversityPeterboroughCanada

Personalised recommendations