Skip to main content

Unifying Ourselves As Efficacious, Autonomous and Creative Beings – Kant on Moral Education As a Process Without Fixed Ends

  • Chapter
International Handbook of Philosophy of Education

Part of the book series: Springer International Handbooks of Education ((SIHE))

Abstract

It is argued with Immanuel Kant that we as human beings ought to unify ourselves as efficacious, autonomous and creative beings, and that moral education is an open-ended and never-ending process. It is also argued that we wilfully deviate from unifying ourselves in the terms mentioned above due to our imperfect rational nature. This, however, does not suggest that we should not be able to unify ourselves in the terms suggested. On the contrary, the efforts to render ourselves efficacious, autonomous and creative should remain. It seems, however, that education in present times influences children and young people to render themselves efficacious with regard to specific desired ends, as well as being loyal and morally committed to how things stand, instead of making it possible for them to unify themselves in the above-mentioned sense. Education is therefore not an open-ended and never-ending process in moral terms.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 669.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 849.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 849.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See Guyer 2014b, for a discussion on this.

  2. 2.

    See, for example, Korsgaard 2008 and 2009.

  3. 3.

    See, for example, Allison 2001, Chapter 12, Bruno 2010, Chapter 4, Crowther 2010, pp. 147–152, Guyer 1997, pp. 355–361, and 2014a, Chapter 9, for discussions on Kant’s notion of creativity, in particular genius.

  4. 4.

    See Kant 1997, in particular Chapters II–IX, and Kant 2000, § 84, 86, 87 and 91 for discussions on the notion of the highest good.

  5. 5.

    See also Guyer, (2006) for a discussion on three different interpretations of the free play between imagination and understanding, namely the precognitive, the multicognitive and the metacognitive approach, which Guyer defends. The precognitive approach suggests that ‘free play’ means playing around with images which would not be constrained by any determinate concepts, and the multicognitive approach suggests that ‘free play’ means playing around with concepts which would not be determined or constrained by any determinate concepts, which Guyer argues are dubious (see 2006, p. 178). He argues instead that “the only way we can understand Kant’s account of the free play of the cognitive powers consistently with our own and his assumptions about the determinacy of the objects of aesthetic judgment, as well as with his assumption about the judgmental and therefore object-referring structure of consciousness itself, is by replacing the precognitive and multicognitive approaches with what I will now call a ‘metacognitive’ approach. [And Guyer continues:] On such an approach, the free and harmonious play of imagination and understanding should be understood as a state of mind in which the manifold of intuition induced by the perception of an object and presented by the imagination to the understanding is recognized to satisfy the rules for the organization of that manifold dictated by the determinate concept or concepts on which our recognition and identification of the object of this experience depends. It is also a state of mind in which it is felt that – or as if – the understanding’s underlying objective or interest in unity is being satisfied in a way that goes beyond anything required for or dictated by satisfaction of the determinate concept or concepts on which mere identification of the object depends.” (Guyer 2006, pp. 182–183)

  6. 6.

    See Kant 2000, 5: 295 and 2006, §43 for discussions on three maxims of human understanding; see also Deligiorgi 2002, Merritt 2009, Roth 2011 and 2015, for discussions on this and similar issues.

  7. 7.

    See also Munzel 1999 for a discussion on the value of cultivating reflective judgment in education and elsewhere.

  8. 8.

    See Korsgaard 2008, 2009, where she develops a view of agency in terms of efficacy and autonomy, but not creativity, with regard to Kant’s principles of practical reason, namely the hypothetical and categorical imperative; see Kant 1998b, in particular Section II for a discussion on these principles.

  9. 9.

    See also Roth 2014 for a discussion on this and similar issues.

  10. 10.

    See Guyer 2000b for a discussion on morally permissible ends.

  11. 11.

    See Kant 2000, §42, §59; see also Baxley 2005 and Guyer 2005 for discussions on this.

  12. 12.

    See Kant 1998c, 6: 21, 38, 43, and Kant 2006, p. 229 for discussions on evil being innate.

  13. 13.

    See also Korsgaard 2009, in particular Chapter 4.4, for a similar argument.

  14. 14.

    See Dewey’s German Philosophy and Politics, 1915/1979 in which he strangely argues that Kant defends the idea that those who do their duty submit themselves to the will of others and follow their orders. It seems that Dewey mistakenly associated duty with heteronomy instead of autonomy, and that he therefore thinks that Kant defends the absurd idea that doing one’s duty consists in following orders, and hence not thinking for oneself, from the standpoint of the other, and consistently; see also Campbell 2004 and Johnston 2006 for critical discussions on Dewey’s reception of German philosophy in general and Kant’s in particular in his German Philosophy and Politics.

  15. 15.

    See Kant 2006, 324 and 2007, 9: 450 for the value of cultivating, civilizing, and moralizing ourselves in education and elsewhere.

  16. 16.

    See Rönnström 2012, 2015 and Wahlström 2015 for discussions on this and similar issues.

  17. 17.

    See, for example, Biesta 2010; Lingard, Martino and Rezai-Rashti (Eds.) (2015) and Smith (Ed.) (2016) for critical discussions on this and similar issues.

  18. 18.

    See Roth 2012b and 2015 for discussion on this and similar issues.

  19. 19.

    See Roth 2012a, 2014 and 2015 for discussions on this.

  20. 20.

    See also Surprenant 2014 for a discussion on the value of cultivating virtue in education and elsewhere in Kantian terms.

References

  • Allison, H. E. (1995). Kant’s theory of freedom. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Allison, H. E. (2001). Kant’s theory of taste. A reading of the critique of aesthetic judgment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Baxley, A. M. (2005). The practical significance of taste in Kant’s “Critique of Judgment”: Love of natural beauty as a mark of moral character. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 63(1), 33–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Biesta, G. (2010). Good education in an age of measurement – Ethics, politics, democracy. London/New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bruno, P. M. (2010). Kant’s concept of genius. its origin and function in the third critique, Continuum studies in philosophy. London: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campell, J. (2004). Dewey and German philosophy in wartime. Transactions of the Charles S. Pierce Society, 40(1), 1–20.

    Google Scholar 

  • Collins, L. (1997). From the lectures of Professor Kant, Königsberg, Winter Semester, 1784-5, In Lectures on ethics (P. Heath, Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crowther, P. (2010). The Kantian aesthetic. From knowledge to the Avant-Garde. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Deligiorgi, K. (2002). Universalisability, publicity, and communication: Kant’s conception of reason. European Journal of Philosophy, 10(2), 143–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1915/1979). German philosophy and politics. In J. A. Boydston (Ed.), John Dewey, The middle works, 1899–1924 (Vol. 8, pp. 135–204). Carbondale/Dewardsville: Southern Illinois University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guyer, P. (1997). Kant and the claims of taste. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guyer, P. (2000a). Editor’s introduction. In Immanuel Kant, Critique of the power of judgment (pp. xiii–lii), edited by Paul Guyer, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guyer, P. (2000b). Nature, freedom, and happiness: The third proposition of Kant’s idea for a universal history. In his Kant on freedom, law, and happiness (pp. 372–407). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guyer, P. (2005). The symbols of freedom in Kant’s aesthetics. In his Values of beauty – Historical essays in aesthetics (pp. 222–241). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guyer, P. (2006). The harmony of the faculties revisited. In R. Kukla (Ed.), Aesthetics and cognition in Kant’s critical philosophy (pp. 162–193). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guyer, P. (2014a). Kant. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guyer, P. (2014b). Examples of perfectionism. Journal of Aesthetic Education, 48(3), 5–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Herman, B. (2007). Training to autonomy: Kant and the question of moral education. In her Moral literacy (pp. 130–153). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnston, J. S. (2006). Dewey’s critique of Kant. Transactions of the Charles S. Pierce Society, 42(4), 518–551.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnston, J. S. (2013). Kant’s philosophy – A study for educators. New York: Bloomsbury Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1996a). The metaphysics of morals, edited by Mary J. Gregor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1996b). An answer to the question: What is enlightenment? In M. J. Gregor (Ed.), Practical philosophy (pp. 17–22). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1997) Critique of practical reason, edited by Mary J. Gregor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1998a). In P. Guyer & A. W. Wood (Eds.), Critique of pure reason. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1998b). In M. J. Gregor (Ed.), Groundwork of the metaphysics of morals. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1998c). In A. W. Wood & G. di Giovanni (Eds.), Religion within the boundaries of mere reason. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (2000) Critique of the power of judgment, edited by Paul Guyer. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (2006). In R. B. Louden (Ed.), Anthropology from a pragmatic point of view. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (2007). Lectures on pedagogy. In G. Zöller & R. B. Louden (Eds.), Anthropology, history, and education (pp. 434–485). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (2009). Idea for a universal history with a cosmopolitan aim. In E. O. Rorty & J. Schmidt (Eds.), Idea for a universal history with a cosmopolitan aim – A critical guide (pp. 9–23). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard, C. (1996). Kant’s formula of humanity. In her Creating the kingdom of ends (pp. 106–132). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard, C. (2004). Fellow creatures: Kantian ethics and our duties to animals, The Tanner lectures on human values. Delivered at University of Michigan, USA, February 6, 2004.

    Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard, C. (2008). The constitution of agency: Essays on practical reason and moral psychology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard, C. (2009). Self-constitution: Agency, identity, and integrity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lingard, B., Martino, W., & Rezai-Rashti, G. (Eds.). (2015). Testing regimes, accountabilities and education policy. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Louden, R. (2011). Becoming human: Kant and the philosophy of education. In his Kant’s human being – Essays on his theory of human nature (pp. 136–150). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Merritt, M. (2009). Reflection, enlightenment, and the significance of spontaneity in Kant. British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 17(5), 981–1010.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moran, K. A. (2012). Moral education and moral progress. In her Community and progress in Kant’s moral philosophy (pp. 127–167). Washington, DC: The Catholic University of America Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Munzel, G. F. (1999). Kant’s conception of moral character – The critical link of morality, anthropology, and reflective judgment. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Munzel, G. F. (2012). Kant’s conception of pedagogy – Toward education for freedom. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rönnström, N. (2012). From globalist to cosmopolitan learning: on the reflexive modernization of teacher education. Ethics & Global Politics, 5(4), 193–216.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rönnström, N. (2015). Educating competitive teachers for a competitive nation? Policy Futures in Education, 13(6), 732–750.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roth, K. (2011). Understanding agency and educating character. Educational Theory, 61(3), 257–274.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roth, K. (2012a). Freedom and autonomy in knowledge-based societies. In K. Roth & C. W. Surprenant (Eds.), Kant and education – Interpretations and commentary (pp. 214–225). New York/London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roth, K. (2012b). A cosmopolitan design of teacher education and a progressive orientation towards the highest good. Ethics & Global Politics, 5(4), 259–279.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roth, K. (2014). Making ourselves intelligible – Rendering ourselves efficacious and autonomous, without fixed ends. Journal of Aesthetic Education, 48(3), 28–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roth, K. (2015). The role of examples, current designs and ideas for a cosmopolitan design of education. Policy Futures in Education, 13(6), 763–774.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roth, K., & Selander, S. (2008). Introduction: Changed conditions for identity formation, communication and learning. Studies in Philosophy and Education, 27(4), 207–209.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roth, K., & Surprenant, C. W. (Eds.). (2012). Kant and education – Interpretations and commentary. New York/London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siegel, H. (1988). Educating reason – Rationality, critical thinking and education. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, W. (Ed.). (2016). The global testing culture: Shaping education policy, perceptions and practice. Oxford: Symposium Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Surprenant, C. W. (2014). Moral education and the cultivation of virtue. In his Kant and the cultivation of virtue (pp. 76–107). New York and London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wahlström, N. (2015). Transnational policy discourses on teacher education: A cosmopolitan perspective. Policy Futures in Education, 13(6), 801–816.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wood, A. W. (1970). Kant’s moral religion. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wood, A. W. (2010). Kant and the intelligibility of evil. In S. Anderson-Gold & P. Muchnik (Eds.), Kant’s anatomy of evil. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Klas Roth .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer International Publishing AG, part of Springer Nature

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Roth, K. (2018). Unifying Ourselves As Efficacious, Autonomous and Creative Beings – Kant on Moral Education As a Process Without Fixed Ends. In: Smeyers, P. (eds) International Handbook of Philosophy of Education. Springer International Handbooks of Education. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-72761-5_19

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-72761-5_19

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-72759-2

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-72761-5

  • eBook Packages: EducationEducation (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics