Advertisement

Bio-Agency and the Possibility of Artificial Agents

  • Anne Sophie Meincke
Chapter
Part of the European Studies in Philosophy of Science book series (ESPS, volume 9)

Abstract

Within the philosophy of biology, recently promising steps have been made towards a biologically grounded concept of agency. Agency is described as bio-agency: the intrinsically normative adaptive behaviour of human and non-human organisms, arising from their biological autonomy. My paper assesses the bio-agency approach by examining criticism recently directed by its proponents against the project of embodied robotics. Defenders of the bio-agency approach have claimed that embodied robots do not, and for fundamental reasons cannot, qualify as artificial agents because they do not fully realise biological autonomy. More particularly, it has been claimed that embodied robots fail to be agents because agency essentially requires metabolism. I shall argue that this criticism, while being valuable in bringing to the fore important differences between bio-agents and existing embodied robots, nevertheless is too strong. It relies on inferences from agency-as-we-know-it to agency-as-it-could-be which are justified neither empirically nor conceptually.

Keywords

Bio-agency Biological autonomy Metabolism Normativity Embodied robotics Artificial life 

Notes

Acknowledgments

This paper was funded by the European Research Council, grant agreement number 324186 (“A Process Ontology for Contemporary Biology”). Previous versions of this paper were presented in September 2015 at the Internal “Physics and Philosophy” workshop of the Research Project “Agency and (Quantum) Mechanics” (funded by the Templeton World Charity Foundation) in Reichenau at Lake Constance in Germany, in March 2016 at the 2016 Conference of the German Society of the Philosophy of Science (GWP) in Düsseldorf in Germany and in June 2016 at the 2016 meeting of Philosophy of Biology in the UK (PBUK) in Bristol in the United Kingdom. I am grateful to the organisers and audiences, especially Hans F. Briegel, Thomas Müller and Josef Quitterer, for helpful discussions and suggestions. I am also grateful to John Dupré and an anonymous referee for helpful comments on an earlier draft of this paper.

References

  1. Alberghina, L., and H.V. Westerhoff, eds. 2005. Systems biology: Definitions and perspectives. Berlin/Heidelberg: Springer.Google Scholar
  2. Arnellos, A., and A. Moreno. 2015. Multicellular agency: An organizational view. Biology and Philosophy 30: 333–357.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Arnellos, A., T. Spyrou, and J. Darzentas. 2010. Towards the naturalization of agency based on an interactivist account of autonomy. New Ideas in Psychology 28: 296–311.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Bagatolli, L., J.H. Ipsen, A.H. Simonsen, and O.G. Mouritsen. 2010. An outlook on organization of lipids in membranes: Searching for a realistic connection with the organization of biological membranes. Progress in Lipid Research 49: 378–389.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Ball, P. 2008. Water as an active constituent in cell biology. Chemical Reviews 108: 74–108.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Barandiaran, X., and A. Moreno. 2006. On what makes certain dynamical systems cognitive: A minimally cognitive organization program. Adaptive Behavior 14: 171–185.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. ———. 2008. Adaptivity: From metabolism to behavior. Adaptive Behavior 16: 325–344.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Barandiaran, X., E. di Paolo, and M. Rohde. 2009. Defining agency: Individuality, normativity, asymmetry, and spatio-temporality in action. Adaptive Behavior 17: 367–386.Google Scholar
  9. Bishop, J. 1989. Natural agency. An essay on the causal theory of action. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  10. Boden, M. 1999. Is metabolism necessary? British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 50: 231–248.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Boogerd, F.C., F.J. Bruggeman, J.-H.S. Hofmeyr, and H.V. Westerhoff, eds. 2007. Systems biology: Philosophical foundations. Amsterdam et al.: Elsevier.Google Scholar
  12. Braitenberg, V. 1984. Vehicles: Experiments in synthetic psychology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  13. Brembs, B. 2011. Towards a scientific concept of free will as a biological trait: Spontaneous actions and decision-making in invertebrates. Proceedings of the Royal Society 278: 930–939.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Brooks, R. 1991a. Intelligence without representation. Artificial Intelligence 47: 139–159.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. ———. 1991b. Intelligence without reason. In Proceedings of 12th international joint conference on artificial intelligence, 569–595. Sydney, Australia: Morgan Kaufman publishers.Google Scholar
  16. Campbell, R. 2010. The emergence of action. New Ideas in Psychology 28: 283–295.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Clark, A. 1997. Being there: Putting mind, world, and body back together. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  18. Davidson, D. 1980. Essays on actions and events. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  19. De Jesus, P. 2016. Autopoietic enactivism, phenomenology and the deep continuity between life and mind. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 15: 265–289.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Di Paolo, E. 2003. Organismically-inspired robotics: Homeostatic adaptation and teleology beyond the closed sensorimotor loop. In Dynamical systems approach to embodiment and sociality, ed. K. Murase and T. Asakura, 19–42. Adelaide: Advanced Knowledge International.Google Scholar
  21. ———. 2009. Extended life. Topoi 28: 9–21.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. ———. 2010. Robotics inspired in the organism. Intellectica 53 (54): 129–162.Google Scholar
  23. Dupré, J. 2012. Processes of life. Essays in the philosophy of biology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. ———. 2013. How much of the free will problem does (the right kind of) indeterminism solve? Philosophical Inquiries 1: 79–92.Google Scholar
  25. Froese, T., and T. Ziemke. 2009. Enactive artificial intelligence: Investigating the systemic organization of life and mind. Artificial Intelligence 173: 466–500.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Gilbert, S.F., and A.I. Tauber. 2016. Rethinking individuality: The dialectics of the holobiont. Biology and Philosophy 31: 839–853.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Gilbert, S.F., J. Sapp, and A.I. Tauber. 2012. A symbiotic view of life: We have never been individuals. Quarterly Review of Biology 87: 325–341.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Haselager, W.F.G. 2005. Robotics, philosophy and the problems of autonomy. Pragmatics & Cognition 13: 515–532.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Jonas, H. 1968. Biological foundations of individuality. International Philosophical Quarterly 8: 231–251.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. ———. 2001 (1966). The phenomenon of life. Toward a philosophical biology. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.Google Scholar
  31. Kim, S., C. Laschi, and B. Trimmer. 2013. Soft robotics: A bioinspired evolution in robotics. Trends in Biotechnology 31: 287–294.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Kirschner, M., J. Gerhart, and T. Mitchison. 2000. Molecular ‘Vitalism’. Cell 100: 79–88.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Langton, C.G. 1989. Artificial life. In Artificial life, ed. C.G. Langton, 1–47. Redwood City: Addison-Wesley.Google Scholar
  34. Maturana, H.R., and F.J. Varela. 1980. Autopoiesis and cognition: The realization of the living (Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science). Dordrecht et al.: Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. ———. 1987. The tree of knowledge: The biological roots of human understanding. Boston: Shambhala.Google Scholar
  36. Meincke, A.S. forthcoming. Persons as biological processes. A bio-processual solution to the personal identity dilemma. In Everything flows. Towards a processual philosophy of biology, ed. D. Nicholson and J. Dupré. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  37. Meincke, A. S. in preparation a. Autopoiesis, biological autonomy and the process view of life.Google Scholar
  38. Meincke, A. S. in preparation b. Bio-powers and free will.Google Scholar
  39. Moreno, A., and M. Mossio. 2015. Biological autonomy. A philosophical and theoretical enquiry. Dordrecht: Springer. (History and theory of the life sciences 12).Google Scholar
  40. Moreno, A., and A. Etxeberria. 2005. Agency in Natural and Artificial Systems. Artificial Life 11: 161–175.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Moreno, A., A. Etxeberria, and J. Umerez. 1994. Universality without matter? In Artificial life IV, ed. R.A. Brooks and P. Maes, 406–410. Cambridge, MA/London: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  42. Nicholson, D. 2013. Organisms ≠ machines. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science. Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 44: 669–678.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. Nicholson, D., and J. Dupré, eds. forthcoming. Everything flows. Towards a processual philosophy of biology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  44. Noble, D. 2006. The music of life. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  45. O’Malley, M.A., and J. Dupré. 2005. Fundamental issues in systems biology. BioEssays 27: 1270–1276.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. Rosen, R. 1991. Life itself. A comprehensive inquiry into the nature, origin and fabrication of life. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
  47. Rosslenbroich, B. 2014. On the origin of autonomy. A new look at the major transitions in evolution. Cham et al.: Springer.Google Scholar
  48. Ruiz-Mirazo, K., and A. Moreno. 2004. Basic autonomy as a fundamental step in the synthesis of life. Artificial Life 10: 235–259.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  49. Schlosser, A. 2015. Agency. In The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, ed. E.N. Zalta, Fall 2015 edn. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2015/entries/agency/
  50. Shapiro, L. 2010. Embodied cognition. London/New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
  51. Skewes, J.C., and C.A. Hooker. 2009. Bio-agency and the problem of action. Biology and Philosophy 24: 283–300.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  52. Spann, A. S. (née Meincke). 2014. Bio-agency: Können Organismen handeln? In Vermögen und Handlung. Der dispositionale Realismus und unser Selbstverständnis als Handelnde, ed. A.S. Spann and D. Wehinger, 191–224. Münster: Mentis.Google Scholar
  53. Steels, L., and R. Brooks. 1995. The artificial life route to artificial intelligence: Building embodied, situated agents. New Haven: Lawrence Erlbaum Assoc..Google Scholar
  54. Steward, H. 2012. A metaphysics for freedom. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  55. Thompson, E. 2007. Mind in life: Biology, phenomenology, and the sciences of mind. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  56. Trivedi, D., C.D. Rahn, W.M. Kier, and I.D. Walker. 2008. Soft robotics: Biological inspiration, state of the art, and future research. Applied Bionics and Biomechanics 5: 99–117.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  57. Varela, F.J. 1979. Principles of Biological Autonomy (The North-Holland Series in General Systems Research 2). New York: Elsevier.Google Scholar
  58. ———. 1995. The re-enchantment of the concrete. In The artificial life route to artificial intelligence: Building embodied, situated agents, ed. L. Steels and R. Brooks, 11–20. New Haven: Lawrence Erlbaum Assoc.Google Scholar
  59. ———. 1996. Neurophenomenology: A methodological remedy for the hard problem. Journal of Consciousness Studies 3: 330–349.Google Scholar
  60. ———. 1997. Patterns of life: Intertwining identity and cognition. Brain and Cognition 34: 72–87.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  61. Varela, F.J., E. Thomson, and E. Rosch. 1991. The embodied mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  62. Ziemke, T. 2016. The body of knowledge: On the role of the living body in grounding cognition. Biosystems 148: 4–11.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer International Publishing AG, part of Springer Nature 2018

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of Sociology, Philosophy and AnthropologyUniversity of ExeterExeterUK

Personalised recommendations