Advertisement

Models in Search of Targets: Exploratory Modelling and the Case of Turing Patterns

  • Axel Gelfert
Chapter
Part of the European Studies in Philosophy of Science book series (ESPS, volume 9)

Abstract

Traditional frameworks for evaluating scientific models have tended to downplay their exploratory function; instead they emphasize how models are inherently intended for specific phenomena and are to be judged by their ability to predict, reproduce, or explain empirical observations. By contrast, this paper argues that exploration should stand alongside explanation, prediction, and representation as a core function of scientific models. Thus, models often serve as starting points for future inquiry, as proofs of principle, as sources of potential explanations, and as a tool for reassessing the suitability of the target system (and sometimes of whole research agendas). This is illustrated by a case study of the varied career of reaction-diffusion models in the study of biological pattern formation, which was initiated by Alan Turing in a classic 1952 paper. Initially regarded as mathematically elegant, but biologically irrelevant, demonstrations of how, in principle, spontaneous pattern formation could occur in an organism, such Turing models have only recently rebounded, thanks to advances in experimental techniques and computational methods. The long-delayed vindication of Turing’s initial model, it is argued, is best explained by recognizing it as an exploratory tool (rather than as a purported representation of an actual target system).

Keywords

Exploratory models Scientific modelling Models Turing patterns Reaction-diffusion systems 

Notes

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank the conference participants at the GWP. 2016 meeting in Düsseldorf in March 2016 and at the workshop “Models in Science”, held at Lingnan University (Hong Kong) in March 2017, for their discussion and feedback. An anonymous referee provided especially helpful and incisive comments, for which I am grateful. Professor Shigeru Kondo at Osaka University kindly gave permission to reproduce the two images labelled as Figs. 14.3 and 14.4 above.

References

  1. Arabatzis, T. 2006. On the inextricability of the context of discovery and the context of justification. In Revisiting discovery and justification, ed. J. Schickore and F. Steinle, 215–230. Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Burian, R.M. 1997. Exploratory experimentation and the role of histochemical techniques in the work of Jean Brachet, 1938–1952. History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 19 (1): 27–45.Google Scholar
  3. Elliott, K.C. 2007. Varieties of exploratory experimentation in nanotoxicology. History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 29 (3): 313–336.Google Scholar
  4. Gelfert, A. 2009. Rigorous results, cross-model justification, and the transfer of empirical warrant. Synthese 169 (3): 497–519.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. ———. 2011. Mathematical formalisms in scientific practice: From denotation to model-based representation. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 42 (2): 272–286.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. ———. 2014. Applicability, indispensability, and underdetermination: Puzzling over Wigner’s ‘unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics’. Science & Education 23 (5): 997–1009.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. ———. 2016. How to do science with models: A philosophical primer. New York: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. ———. 2017. The ontology of models. In Springer handbook of model-based science, ed. L. Magnani and T. Bertolotti, 5–23. Heidelberg: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Green, J.B., and J. Sharpe. 2015. Positional information and reaction-diffusion: Two big ideas in developmental biology combine. Development 142 (7): 1203–1211.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Hanson, N.R. 1960. Is there a logic of scientific discovery? Australasian Journal of Philosophy 38 (2): 91–106.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Harman, P.M. 1998. The natural philosophy of James Clerk Maxwell. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  12. Hoyningen-Huene, P. 2006. Context of discovery versus context of justification and Thomas Kuhn. In Revisiting discovery and justification, ed. J. Schickore and F. Steinle, 119–131. Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Kondo, S., and R. Asai. 1995. A reaction-diffusion wave on the skin of the marine angelfish Pomacanthus. Nature 376: 765–768.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Kondo, S., and T. Miura. 2010. Reaction-diffusion model as a framework for understanding biological pattern formation. Science 329 (5999): 1616–1620.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Magnani, L. 2004. Model-based and manipulative abduction in science. Foundations of Science 9 (3): 219–247.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Maini, P.K., R.E. Baker, and C.-M. Chuong. 2006. The Turing model comes of molecular age. Science 314 (5804): 1397–1398.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Maxwell, J.C. 1890. On physical lines of force. In Scientific papers of James Clerk Maxwell, ed. W.D. Niven, 451–513. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  18. Meyer, H. 1951. On the heuristic value of scientific models. Philosophy of Science 18 (2): 111–123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Morrison, M. 1999. Models as autonomous agents. In Models as mediators: Perspectives on natural and social science, ed. M. Morgan and M. Morrison, 38–65. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Morrison, M., and M. Morgan. 1999. Models as mediating instruments. In Models as mediators, ed. M.S. Morgan and M. Morrison, 10–37. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Nersessian, N. 1999. Model-based reasoning in conceptual change. In Model-based reasoning in scientific discovery, ed. L. Magnani, N. Nersessian, and P. Thagard, 5–22. New York: Plenum Publishers.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Newman, S.A., and H.L. Frisch. 1979. Dynamics of skeletal pattern formation in developing chick limb. Science 205 (4407): 662–668.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Nickles, T. 1985. Beyond divorce: Current status of the discovery debate. Philosophy of Science 52 (2): 177–206.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. ———. 2006. Heuristic appraisal: Context of discovery or justification? In Revisiting discovery and justification, ed. J. Schickore and F. Steinle, 159–182. Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Osaka University Pattern Formation Group, n.d. Papers of the Pattern Formation Group. Retrieved March 31, 2017, from http://www.fbs.osaka-u.ac.jp/labs/skondo/publication.html
  26. Pipes, L. 1953. An operational analysis of traffic dynamics. Journal of Applied Physics 24 (3): 274–281.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Reutlinger, A., D. Hangleiter, and S. Hartmann. forthcoming. Understanding (with) toy models. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science.Google Scholar
  28. Rheinberger, H.-J. 2010. An epistemology of the concrete: Twentieth-century histories of life. Durham: Duke University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Saunders, J.W., J.M. Cairns, and M.T. Gasseling. 1957. The role of the apical ridge of ectoderm in the differentiation of the morphological structure and inductive specificity of limb parts in the chick. Journal of Morphology 101 (1): 57–87.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Sheth, R., L. Marcon, M. Bastida, M. Junco, L. Quintana, R. Dahn, and M. Ros. 2012. Hox genes regulate digit patterning by controlling the wavelength of a turing-type mechanism. Science 338 (6113): 1476–1480.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Steele, K., and C. Werndl. forthcoming. Model-selection theory: The need for a more nuanced picture of use-novelty and double-counting. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science Google Scholar
  32. Steinle, F. 1997. Entering new fields: Exploratory uses of experimentation. Philosophy of Science 64(Proceedings of the PSA1996, Pt. II) S65–S74.Google Scholar
  33. Suárez, M. 1999. The role of models in the application of scientific theories: Epistemological implications. In Models as mediators: Perspectives on natural and social science, ed. M.S. Morgan and M. Morrison, 168–195. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Taylor, P. 1989. Revising models and generating theory. Oikos 54 (1): 121–126.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Thompson, D.W. 1917. On growth and form. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Turing, A. 1952. The chemical basis of morphogenesis. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London. Series B, Biological Sciences (641): 37–72.Google Scholar
  37. Wageningen-Kessels, F.V., H. van Lint, K. Vuik, and S. Hoogendoorn. 2015. A genealogy of traffic flow models. EURO Journal on Transportation and Logistics 4 (4): 445–473.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Waters, C.K. 2007. The nature and context of exploratory experimentation: An introduction to three case studies of exploratory research. History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 29 (3): 275–284.Google Scholar
  39. Weisberg, M. 2007. Who is a modeler? British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 58: 207–233.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Wimsatt, W.C. 2007. Re-engineering philosophy for limited beings: Piecewise approximations to reality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  41. Wolpert, L. 1969. Positional information and the spatial pattern of cellular differentiation. Journal of Theoretical Biology 25 (1): 1–47.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Wolpert, L., C. Tickle, and A. Martinez Arias. 2015. Principles of development. 5th ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer International Publishing AG, part of Springer Nature 2018

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of Philosophy, Literature, History of Science and TechnologyTechnical University of BerlinBerlinGermany

Personalised recommendations