Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 387))

Abstract

In this paper I describe a construction which can be applied to any many-valued logic to give a plurivalent logic, that is, a logic in which formulas may take more than one value. Various results are established concerning the relationship between the many-valued logic and the corresponding plurivalent logic; and a detailed analysis is provided of the relationship between the two for a small family of many-valued logics related to the logic of First Degree Entailment.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    For a detailed description of Imaginary Logic, see Priest (2000).

  2. 2.

    What follows is published as ‘Plurivalent Logic’, Australasian Journal of Logic, 12 (2014), pp. 2–13. It is reprinted with their permission.

  3. 3.

    In particular, it is deployed in Priest (1984, 2008b, 2010, 2014). These papers can be consulted for some of the philosophical considerations which might motivate such a construction. The point of the present paper is simply to spell out its technical details.

  4. 4.

    See Priest (2008a), ch. 7.

  5. 5.

    An interesting alternative is to define ‘\(\vartriangleright \) designates A’ as: for all v such that \(A\vartriangleright v\), v ∈ D. I defer discussion of this possibility to a brief appendix to the paper.

  6. 6.

    These can be found in Czelakowski (2001), esp. Prop 0.3.3.

  7. 7.

    Priest (2010) and (2015) call the logic this generates FDE φ .

  8. 8.

    See Priest (2008a), ch. 7. For B 3, see Haack (1996), pp. 169–70.

  9. 9.

    Many thanks to Thomas Ferguson for drawing my attention to this.

  10. 10.

    See Priest (1984).

  11. 11.

    For b this is proved by a model theoretic construction in Priest (1984). I generalise this in the next section. For bn and bne, the results are proved in Priest (2010) and (2015), respectively, by considering proof theories for these logics.

  12. 12.

    It is worth noting that Shramko and Wansing (2011), chs. 3 and 4, show how, given any univalent logic M, to construct a logic whose values are the values of \(\ddot {M}\). Given their approach, it is natural to think of the empty set not simply as an absence of values, but as a positive value in its own right. This motivates different possible definitions for the truth functions in the logic, producing somewhat different results. In particular, with these definitions, the empty set does not generate a failure of ∨-introduction. In this context, it is worth noting that applying plurivalence to classical logic does not produce FDE.

  13. 13.

    This is done for classical logic and positive plurivalence in Priest (1984).

  14. 14.

    For the limit: anything valid in the limit logic is valid in each finite “approximation”. Conversely, anything invalid in it is invalid in some approximation, since only finitely many values are employed in the counter-model.

  15. 15.

    The construction is used, in effect, in Priest (1995, 2005), ch. 8.

  16. 16.

    Many thanks go to Lloyd Humberstone for very helpful comments on an earlier draft of this paper.

References

  • Czelakowski, J. (2001). Protoalgebraic logics. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Haack, S. (1996). Deviant logic, fuzzy logic: Beyond the formalism. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oller, C. (1999). Paraconsistency and analyticity. Logic and Logical Philosophy, 7, 91–99.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Priest, G. (1984). Hypercontradictions. Logique et Analyse, 107, 237–243.

    Google Scholar 

  • Priest, G. (1995). Multiple denotation, ambiguity, and the strange case of the missing amoeba. Logique et Analyse, 38, 361–373.

    Google Scholar 

  • Priest, G. (2000). Vasil’év and imaginary logic’. History and Philosophy of Logic, 21, 135–146.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Priest, G. (2005) (2nd ed. 2016). Towards non-being. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Priest, G. (2008a). Introduction to non-classical logics: From if to is. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Priest, G. (2008b). Jaina logic: A contemporary perspective. History and Philosophy of Logic, 29, 263–278.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Priest, G. (2010). The logic of the Catuṣkoṭi. Comparative Philosophy, 1, 32–54.

    Google Scholar 

  • Priest, G. (2015). None of the above: The logic of the Catuṣkoṭi, ch. 24. In J. Y. Beziau, M. Chakraborty, & S Ditta (Eds.), New directions in paraconsistent logic. New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Priest, G. (2014). Speaking of the ineffable. In J.-L. Liu & D. Berger (Eds.), Nothingness in Asian philosophy. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shramko, Y., & Wansing, H. (2011). Truth and falsity: An inquiry into generalized truth values. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Graham Priest .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Appendix

Appendix

This appendix concerns a variation of the definition of designation for plurivalent logics. Specifically, we replace the definition of designation of Sect. 12.2 by: ‘\(\vartriangleright \) designates A’ as: for all v such that \(A\vartriangleright v\), v ∈ D. This changes nothing till Sect. 12.5, except the definition of the designated values in \(\dot {M}\), where the modification required is obvious. For Sect. 12.5, let M n be the semantics obtained from M by adding the value n, if necessary. Then line (6) holds provided we replace M b with M n. The homomorphism that establishes this is defined as follows:

  • if e ∈ X then θ(X) = e

  • else: if n ∈ X then θ(X) = n

  • else: if t ∈ X and f ∈ X then θ(X) = n

  • else:

    • if X = {t, b} then θ(X) = t

    • if X = {t, f} then θ(X) = f

    • if X = {x} then θ(X) = x

One may check that this is a homomorphism, and that it is onto.

Things are quite different with respect to the general plurivalence of Sect. 12.6, however; and matters do not modify in such a straightforward way. In particular, the alignment between \(\models _{p}^{M^{e}}\) and \(\models _{g}^{M}\) disappears in both directions. Thus, for M take classical logic (). Then, as one may check, \(p\wedge q\models _{p}^{e}p\), \(p\wedge q\nvDash _{g}^{\emptyset }p\) (let \(\vartriangleright \) relate q to just f, and p to nothing); and \(p\nvDash _{p}^{e}p\vee q\), but \(p\models _{g}^{\emptyset }p\vee q\) (for a counter-model, p must relate to just t; all the values of p ∨ q are then designated—even when q relates to nothing!). What one can say to characterise general plurivalence in this case is still an open question.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Priest, G. (2017). Plurivalent Logics. In: Markin, V., Zaitsev, D. (eds) The Logical Legacy of Nikolai Vasiliev and Modern Logic. Synthese Library, vol 387. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-66162-9_12

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics