Skip to main content

The Challenge of Insufficient Binding

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Real Fourdimensionalism

Part of the book series: Philosophical Studies Series ((PSSP,volume 130))

  • 195 Accesses

Abstract

The fifth chapter sets up the challenge of insufficient binding as a relatively new problem for 4-dimensionalism, and in particular for the stage theory. I argue that the ontology of temporal counterpart relations is underspecified. I explicate this claim discussing various theories of persistence, which can be explicitly or implicitly understood as versions of the stage theory. The chapter ends my discussion of 4-dimensionalism and its challenges.

The sensible fourdimensionalist will claim that current temporal parts are caused to exist by previous temporal parts.

(Sider 2001, 217)

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 79.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    For a similar analysis, see Heller (1984, section 5).

  2. 2.

    For a more detailed analysis I refer to Sect. 2.3.2 of the first part.

  3. 3.

    Additions in […] by the author.

  4. 4.

    Additions in […] by the author.

  5. 5.

    The following figures are inspired by Jonathan Schaffer’s article on The Metaphysics of Causation (2016, n.p.).

  6. 6.

    I would like to thank Roland Poellinger from the Munich Center for Mathematical Philosophy for discussing these concepts with me.

  7. 7.

    Additions in italics and […] by the author.

  8. 8.

    Additions in […] by the author.

  9. 9.

    There are limits to this presentation and dismissal of EOSR. Christina Schneider has pointed out that there might be special structural relations that in some sense they act as closing function to structural systems. If I understand this idea correctly, then those systems would be self-implementing. French has developed a similar idea:

    [French] emphasized how invariance and constancy of relations literally create objects: they play the role of conditions of accessibility which immediately become conditions of objects of experience. (Morganti 2004, 88)

    If this idea could be further developed, my dismissal EOSR would not be sufficiently warranted. However, the proponents of EOSR admit that this would include an extreme revision of everyday ontology:

    Let us consider the idea that relations need relata. On this view, a purely structural description of the world is impossible in principle because structures are defined by relations, but the latter presuppose related individuals. This objection is flawed because relations obviously need relata only in the traditional view of reality, where by assumption we take individual things as fundamental. French and Ladyman have no difficulty in replying that their proposal requires a deep revision of our conceptual apparatus. They also show that such a revision is possible by referring to already existing work. (Morganti 2004, 98)

    Nevertheless, such a revision would not undermine my project substantially. The revised concept of relations would have to be of a completely different kind, than the relations we normally work with in scientific theories. I therefore assume that those reconceived relations would turn out to behave similarly to the carriers, for which I am going to argue at the end of this section. Ultimately, I suppress this possibility for the sake of a concise argument – but it must be mentioned, at least in an (admittedly lengthy) footnote.

  10. 10.

    Where C(…) denotes the predicate ‘…is a cat’ and M(…) denotes the predicate ‘…sits on a mat’.

  11. 11.

    For a formal definition of the theorem, I refer to Bays (2014, n.p.). For a concise proof, I refer to Boolos (1970, 76–78). For a detailed discussion of the Skolem-theorem and its implication for ramseyfied theories, I refer to Ketland (2004, 287–300).

  12. 12.

    Here you will find a loosely formal substantiation of the skolem theorem for a model with a denumerable universe:

    Consider a first-order-logic model \(\mathcal{L}\) with a denumerable universe, such that \(\mathcal{L}\) can be written as quadruple 〈 \(\mathbb{K}\), \(\mathbb{F}\), \(\mathbb{P}\), ar 〉. \(\mathbb{K}\) denotes the finite set of constants. \(\mathbb{F}\) denotes the set of all the functional terms, such like the normal operation ‘+’. \(\mathbb{P}\) denotes the set of the predicates and ar the arity of \(\mathcal{L}\).

    Consider some mapping from the variables of \(\mathcal{L}\) to the predicates. For example Φ:x → Px, where P\(\in \mathbb{P}\). Surely, a sentence of the form ‘Px’ is an item of \(\mathcal{L}\). Let us, therefore, call \(\mathcal{L}\) the respective maximal model.

    Nevertheless, when considering models we are interested in the preservation of truth-values of propositions. Thus, we can define two models to be equivalent (Newman 1928, 139), if they range over the same set of constants and if they give rise to the same distribution of truth-values.

    Further, consider a model \(\mathcal{L}\)* such that \(\mathcal{L}\)* is identical to \(\mathcal{L}\) only \(\mathcal{L}\)* has no free variables. This implies that this model reaches only over the set of constants. We can call \(\mathcal{L}\)* the \(\mathbb{K}\)-model. Trivially, \(\mathcal{L}\)* is finite, because the set \(\mathbb{K}\) was defined to be finite.

    But: \(\mathcal{L}\) and \(\mathcal{L}\)* give rise to the same distribution of truth values. Why? Well, just because for any formula Px it holds true, that only the respective constants bring about truth-values – for example Pa. And since \(\mathcal{L}\) and \(\mathcal{L}\)* differ only in their free variables, this means that for any formula it holds true that if the formula is true in \(\mathcal{L}\), then it is true in \(\mathcal{L}\)* (and vice versa). This means that \(\mathcal{L}\) and \(\mathcal{L}\)* are equivalent in the sense discussed above.

    Q.E.D. This proofs Skolem’s theorem.

  13. 13.

    Additions in […] by the author.

  14. 14.

    The following argument has been developed by David Oderberg (2012, 6–9). I will merely give a re-formulation of it here.

  15. 15.

    Additions in […] by the author.

  16. 16.

    Personally, I do not think that Balashov’s definition of exdurance is consistent. To me it seems utterly unclear, how some thing can be said to be exactly located and LOCATED multiply at the same time. Because of this problem, I will not follow Balashov’s line of reasoning within the context of the following considerations – in particular Chap. 3 of this essay. Marc Andree Weber has pointed me to another serious problem: It seems like certain seemingly equivalent definitions of Balashov’s are not logically equivalent: for example D12 and D13.

  17. 17.

    The paper can be made available by the author.

    Another important remark: In the following section, I am going to use a fairly technical, mathematical terminology. Thus, terms like ‘field’ (in German: Körper) are defined by their mathematical meaning.

References

  • Balashov, Yuri. 2006. Defining ‘Exdurance’. Philosophical Studies 133(1): 143–149.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bays, Timothy. 2014. Skolem’s paradox. Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, Winter 2014. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2014/entries/paradox-skolem/

  • Benovsky, Jiri. 2006. Persistence through time, and across possible worlds. In Epistemische Studien. Schriften zur Erkenntis- und Wissenschaftstheorie. Heusenstamm: Ontos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boolos, George. 1970. A proof of the Löwenheim-Skolem theorem. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 11(1): 76–78.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brüntrup, Godehard. 2009. Natural individuals and intrinsic properties. In Unity and time as problems in metaphysics, ed. Ludger Honnefelder, Edmund Runggaldier, and Benedikt Schick, 237–252. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brüntrup, Godehard. 2011. Panpsychism and structural realism. In The mental as fundamental. New perspectives on panpsychism, ed. Michael Blamauer, 15–34. Heusenstamm: Ontos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, Donald. 1967. Causal relations. The Journal of Philosophy 64(21): 691–703.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dipert, Randall. 1997. The mathematical structure of the world: The world as a graph. The Journal of Philosophy 94(7): 329–358.

    Google Scholar 

  • Erdös, Paul, and Alfréd, Rényi. 1963. Asymmetric graphs. Acta Mathematica Hungarica 14(2): 295–315.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Esfeld, Michael, and Vincent, Lam. 2011. Ontic structural realism as a metaphysics of objects. In Scientific structuralism. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. 281, ed. Alisa Bokulich and Peter Bokulich, 143–159. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawley, Katherine. 2001. How things persist. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawley, Katherine. 2015b. Temporal parts. Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy Winter 2015. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2015/entries/temporal-parts/

  • Heller, Mark. 1984. Temporal parts of fourdimensional objects. Philosophical Studies 46(3): 323–346.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jaskolla, Ludwig. 2011a. Mind matters: Towards a concept of protomental causation. In The mental as fundamental. New perspectives on panpsychism, ed. Michael Blamauer, 57–78. Heusenstamm: Ontos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ketland, Jeffrey. 2004. Empirical adequacy and ramsification. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 55(1): 287–300.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, James, and Don, Ross. 2007. Every thing must go. Metaphysics naturalized. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, James, and Steven, French. 2011. In defence of ontic structural realism. In Scientific Structuralism. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. 281, ed. Alisa Bokulich and Peter Bokulich, 25–42. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, David. 1986b. Counterfactuals. Original 1972, Corrected 1986, Reissued 2001. Hoboken: Wiley Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meixner, Uwe. 2002. Change and change-ersatz. In Individuals, essence and identity, ed. Andrea Bottani, 427–449. Berlin: Kluwer Academic.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Melia, Joseph, and Juha, Saatsi. 2006. Ramseyfication and theoretical content. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 57(3): 561–585.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morganti, Matteo. 2004. On the preferability of epistemic structural realism. Synthese 142(1): 81–107.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Newman, Max. 1928. Mr. Russell’s causal theory of perception. Mind 37(146): 137–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oderberg, David. 2012. The world is not an asymmetric graph. Analysis 71(1): 3–10.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Poincaré, Henri. 1902. La Science et l’Hypothèse. Paris: Flammarion.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, Hilary. 1980. Models and reality. The Journal of Symbolic Logic 45(3): 464–482.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quine, Willard van Orman. 1981. Things and their place in theories. In Theories and things, ed. Willard van Orman Quine, 1–24. Cambrdige, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenberg, Gregg. 2004. A place for consciousness. Probing the deep structure of the natural world. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rugel, Matthias. 2013. Materie – Kausalität – Erleben: Analytische Metaphysik des Panpsychismus. Paderborn: mentis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, Bertrand. 1927. The analysis of mind. Reprint from the 1927 edition. Nottingham: Spokesman Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, Jonathan. 2016. The metaphysics of causation. Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, Fall 2016. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2016/entries/causation-metaphysics/

  • Schneider, Christina. 2011. Leibliche Auferstehung. Provided by the author in February 2011.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shackel, Nicholas. 2011. The world as a graph: Defending metaphysical graphical structuralism. Analysis 71(1): 10–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sider, Ted. 1996. All the worlds a stage. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 74(3): 433–453.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sider, Ted. 2001. Four dimensionalism. An ontology of persistence and time. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sider, Ted. 2004a. Précis of four-dimensionalism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 68(3): 642–647.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sider, Ted. 2004b. Replies to Gallois, Hirsch and Markosian. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 68(3): 674–687.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varzi, Achille. 2003. Naming the stages. Dialectica 57(4): 387–412.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zimmerman, Dean. 1997. Immanent causation. Nous Supplement: Philosophical Perspectives 11. Mind, Causation and World 11(1): 433–471.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Jaskolla, L. (2017). The Challenge of Insufficient Binding. In: Real Fourdimensionalism. Philosophical Studies Series, vol 130. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-65927-5_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics