Advertisement

Conceptions of Genocide and the Ethics of Memorialization

  • Jeffrey Blustein
Chapter

Abstract

Conceptions of genocide can be broadly divided into individualistic and collectivistic. According to the former, genocide is essentially a crime against (many) individuals; according to the latter, it is a crime against a group, which is not reducible to an aggregate of the individuals who belong to it. This chapter argues for the latter on the grounds that it is necessary to capture the distinctive moral evil of genocide. It also argues for a non-consequentialist way of accounting for the ethical value of memorializing genocide. This is called an expressivist approach and three attitudes that memorials may express are highlighted and explored: respect, self-respect, and fidelity to the dead. Different accounts are then presented to explain how these attitudes can belong not only to individuals but also to groups and how, therefore, an expressivist ethic of remembrance for groups is possible. The chapter concludes with a discussion of the principle of warranted self-testifying, according to which those who suffer harm are in an ethically privileged position to testify to it. This principle is applied to group memorialization of genocidal harm, conceived as a group practice.

Keywords

Genocide conceptions Expressivism Respect Self-respect Fidelity to the dead Principle of warranted self-testifying 

Notes

Acknowledgments

I want to thank Dennis Klein, Colleen Murphy, and Margaret Walker for comments on earlier drafts.

References

  1. Abed, M. (2006). Clarifying the concept of genocide. Metaphilosophy, 37(3–4), 308–330.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Anderson, E. (1993). Value in ethics and economics. Cambridge, MA/London: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  3. Anderson, E. (1997). Practical reason and incommensurable goods. In R. Chang (Ed.), Incommensurability, incomparability, and practical reason (pp. 90–110). Cambridge, MA/London: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  4. Anderson, E., & Pildes, R. (2000). Expressive theories of law: A general restatement. University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 148(5), 1503–1576.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Bevernage, B. (2012). “La muerte no existe.” The Madres de Plaza de Mayo and the resistance against the irreversible time of history. In B. Bevernage (Ed.), History, memory, and state sponsored violence (pp. 22–45). New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
  6. Blustein, J. (2008). The moral demands of memory. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Blustein, J. (2014). Forgiveness and remembrance: Remembering wrongdoing in personal and public life. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Boxill, B. (1976). Self-respect and protest. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 6(1), 58–69.Google Scholar
  9. Bratman, M. (1992). Shared cooperative activity. Philosophical Review, 101(2), 327–341.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Bratman, M. (1993). Shared intention. Ethics, 104(1), 327–341.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Bratman, M. (2014). Shared agency: A planning theory of acting together. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Campbell, S. (2014). Our faithfulness to the past: Reconstructing memory value. In S. Campbell, C. M. Koggel, & R. Jacobsen (Eds.), Our faithfulness to the past: The Ethics and Politics of Memory (pp. 30–49). New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Card, C. (2003). Genocide and social death. Hypatia, 18(1), 63–79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Casey, E. (2000). Remembering: A phenomenological study (2nd ed.). Bloomington: Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
  15. Darwall, S. (2004). Respect and the second-person standpoint. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 78, 43–59.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Darwall, S. (2006). The second-personal standpoint: Morality, respect, and accountability. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  17. Digeser, P. (2001). Political forgiveness. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
  18. Eltringham, N., & Maclean, P. (2014). Remembering genocide. In N. Eltringham & P. Maclean (Eds.), Remembering genocide (pp. 1–18). London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  19. Ferreira, M. (2013). Genocide, and its definition as the “partial elimination of a national group”. Genocide Studies and Prevention: An International Journal, 8(1), 5–19.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Gilbert, M. (1989). On social facts. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  21. Gilbert, M. (2000). Sociality and responsibility: New essays in plural subject theory. Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield.Google Scholar
  22. Gilbert, M. (2001). Collective remorse. In A. Jokic (Ed.), War crimes and collective wrongdoing (pp. 216–235). Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  23. Gilbert, M. (2002). Collective guilt and collective guilt feelings. Journal of Ethics, 6(2), 115–143.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Ignatieff, M. (1988). The warrior’s honour: Ethnic war and the modern conscience. London: Chatto & Windus.Google Scholar
  25. Kovach, K. (2006). Genocide and the moral agency of ethnic groups. Metaphilosophy, 37(3–4), 331–352.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Lamb, S. (2006). Forgiveness, women, and responsibility to the group. Journal of Human Rights, 5, 45–60.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Lee, S. (2010). The moral distinctiveness of genocide. Journal of Political Philosophy, 18(3), 335–356.Google Scholar
  28. Lemkin, R. (1944). Axis rule in occupied Europe. Clark: Law Book Exchange.Google Scholar
  29. Logan, T. (2014). National memory and museums: Remembering settler colonial genocide of Indigenous people in Canada. In N. Eltringham & R. Maclean (Eds.), Remembering genocide (pp. 112–130). London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  30. Margalit, A., & Raz, J. (1990). National self–determination. Journal of Philosophy, 87(9), 439–461.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Moses, A. D. (2002). Conceptual blockages and definitional dilemmas in the “racial century”: Genocides of indigenous peoples and the Holocaust. Patterns of Prejudice, 36(4), 19.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Murphy, J. (2002). Forgiveness in counseling: A philosophical perspective. In S. Lamb & J. Murphy (Eds.), Before forgiving: Cautionary views on forgiveness in psychotherapy (pp. 41–53). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Poole, R. (1999). Nation and identity. London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Powell, C. (2007). What do genocides kill? A relational conception of genocide. Journal of Genocide Research, 9(4), 527–547.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Schneewind, J. (1998). The invention of autonomy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  36. Short, D. (2010). Cultural genocide and indigenous people: A sociological approach. International Journal of Human Rights, 14(6), 831–846.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Slote, M. (1983). Goods and virtues. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  38. Smith, E. R., Seeger, C., & Mackie, D. (2007). Can emotions be truly group level? Evidence regarding rour conceptual criteria. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 93(3), 431–446.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. UN CPCG. (1948). Convention on the prevention and punishment of the crime of genocide. Australia, Bulgaria, Cambodia, Ceylon, Czechoslovakia: United Nations.Google Scholar
  40. Volkan, V. (2004). Blind trust: Large groups and their leaders in times of crisis and terror. Charlottesville: Pitchstone.Google Scholar
  41. Young, I. M. (1989). Polity and group difference: A critique of the ideal of universal citizenship. Ethics, 99(2), 250–274.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer International Publishing AG 2018

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.City College, and Graduate CenterCity University of New YorkNew YorkUSA

Personalised recommendations