Skip to main content

Group Knowledge in Interrogative Epistemology

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Book cover Jaakko Hintikka on Knowledge and Game-Theoretical Semantics

Part of the book series: Outstanding Contributions to Logic ((OCTR,volume 12))

Abstract

In this paper we formalize an approach to knowledge that we call Interrogative Epistemology, in the spirit of Hintikka’s “interrogative model” of knowledge. According to our approach, an agent’s knowledge is shaped and limited by her interrogative agenda (as defined by her fundamental questions or “epistemic issues”). The dynamic correlate of this postulate is our Selective Learning principle: the agent’s agenda limits her potential for knowledge-acquisition. Only meaningful information, that is relevant to one’s issues, can really be learnt. We use this approach to propose a new perspective on group knowledge, understood in terms of the epistemic potential of a group of agents: the knowledge that the group may come to possess in common (and thus act upon in a coordinated manner) after all members share their individual information. We argue that the standard notions of group knowledge studied in the literature, ranging from distributed knowledge to common knowledge, do not give us a good measure of a group’s epistemic potential. Common knowledge is too weak and too “static”, focusing on what the agents can coordinate upon only based on their actual, current knowledge (without any intra-group communication), thus disregarding testimonial knowledge. In contrast, the concept of distributed knowledge is too strong, being based on the assumption that agents can completely internalize all the testimonial evidence received from others, irrespective of the limitations posed by their own interrogative agendas. We show that a group’s true epistemic potential typically lies in between common knowledge and distributed knowledge. We propose a logical formalization of these concepts, which comes together with a complete axiomatization, and we use this setting to explain both the triumphs and the failures of collective knowledge, treating examples that range from “collective scientific knowledge” [14, 35, 43] to the so-called “curse of the committee”.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Our restriction to work with a setting in which all answers to a question are mutually exclusive can be lifted if one works with ‘covers’ instead of equivalence relations [21, 24]. However, to keep matters simple, we choose a setting with equivalence relations.

  2. 2.

    Also known as a “UCLA proposition” in logic, and as an “event” in probabilistic terminology.

  3. 3.

    Indeed, the notion of common knowledge traces back to the work of David Lewis [29], who investigated it in the context of analyzing social conventions and their role in coordination.

  4. 4.

    Note that an agent’s issue also includes both answered questions and her open questions.

  5. 5.

    The term ‘summativism’ was introduced by Anthony Quinton in [34] in an epistemic context.

  6. 6.

    Though one should note that a fact can be distributed knowledge without being known to any member of the group: distributed knowledge encompasses everything that is logically entailed by the combination of all the individual pieces of knowledge.

  7. 7.

    We agree that in fact this is still a rough idealization. Other factors should be taken into account when computing group knowledge, e.g. the structure of the group, the various relationships, the degree of mutual trust, each agent’s level’s of expertise etc. But for simplicity, in this paper we focus only on the role of questions.

  8. 8.

    We don’t have a proof of this difference in expressivity, but this conclusion is suggested by the fact that reduction laws do not exist for these logics.

  9. 9.

    We further remark that there are essential technical differences between our setting and the work in inquisitive semantics.

  10. 10.

    In his words, “the trustworthiness of members of epistemic communities is the ultimate foundation for much of our knowledge” (694).

  11. 11.

    See [8] for the definition and properties of canonical models.

  12. 12.

    See [8] for the definition and properties of filtrations.

  13. 13.

    See [8] for the definition and properties of bounded morphisms.

References

  1. Aloni M, Egré P, De Jager T (2013) Knowing whether a or b. Synthese 190(14):2595–2621

    Google Scholar 

  2. Baltag A (2001) Logics for insecure communication. In: Proceedings of the 8th conference on theoretical aspects of rationality and knowledge. Morgan Kaufmann Publishers Inc, pp 111–121

    Google Scholar 

  3. Baltag A, Smets S (2009) Learning by questions and answers: from belief-revision cycles to doxastic fixed points. In: Logic, language, information and computation, Springer, pp 124–139

    Google Scholar 

  4. Baltag A, Moss LS, Solecki S (1998) The logic of public announcements, common knowledge, and private suspicions. In: Proceedings of the 7th conference on theoretical aspects of rationality and knowledge. Morgan Kaufmann Publishers Inc, pp 43–56

    Google Scholar 

  5. Baltag A, van Ditmarsch H, Moss L (2008) Epistemic logic and information update. Handbook of the philosophy of information. Elsevier Science Publishers, Amsterdam, pp 361–456

    Google Scholar 

  6. Barwise J (1988) Three views of common knowledge. In: Proceedings of the 2nd conference on theoretical aspects of reasoning about knowledge. Morgan Kaufmann Publishers Inc, pp 365–379

    Google Scholar 

  7. Belnap ND Jr (1966) Questions, answers, and presuppositions. J Philos 63(20):609–611

    Google Scholar 

  8. Blackburn P, De Rijke M, Venema Y (2002) Modal logic: graph. Darst, vol 53. Cambridge University Press

    Google Scholar 

  9. Boddy R (2014) Epistemic issues and group knowledge. Master’s thesis, University of Amsterdam

    Google Scholar 

  10. Ciardelli I, Roelofsen F (2009) Generalized inquisitive logic: completeness via intuitionistic kripke models. In: Proceedings of the 12th conference on theoretical aspects of rationality and knowledge. ACM, pp 71–80

    Google Scholar 

  11. Coady CA (1992) Testimony: a philosophical study. Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  12. Corlett AJ (1996) Analyzing social knowledge. Rowman & Littlefield Publishers

    Google Scholar 

  13. de Ridder J (2014) Epistemic dependence and collective scientific knowledge. Synthese 191(1):37–53

    Google Scholar 

  14. Fagan M (2012) Collective scientific knowledge. Philos Compass 7(12):821–831

    Article  Google Scholar 

  15. Fagin R, Halpern JY, Vardi MY (1992) What can machines know?: on the properties of knowledge in distributed systems. J ACM (JACM) 39

    Google Scholar 

  16. Fagin R, Moses Y, Vardi MY, Halpern JY (2003) Reasoning about knowledge. MIT press

    Google Scholar 

  17. Gilbert M (1987) Modelling collective belief. Synthese 73(1):185–204

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. Goldman A (2004) Group knowledge versus group rationality: two approaches to social epistemology. Episteme 1(01):11–22

    Google Scholar 

  19. Goldman A, Whitcomb D (eds) (2011) Social epistemology: essential readings. Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  20. Groenendijk J (1999) The logic of interrogation: classical version. Semant linguist theory 9:109–126

    Google Scholar 

  21. Groenendijk J (2007) Inquisitive semantics: two possibilities for disjunction. Springer

    Google Scholar 

  22. Groenendijk J, Stokhof M (1985) On the semantics of questions and the pragmatics of answers. Semant Crit Concepts Linguist 288

    Google Scholar 

  23. Groenendijk J, Stokhof M (1990) Partitioning logical space. Annot Handout

    Google Scholar 

  24. Groenendijk J, Roelofsen E et al (2009) Inquisitive semantics and pragmatics. In: Workshop on language, communication, and rational agency at Stanford

    Google Scholar 

  25. Hardwig J (1991) The role of trust in knowledge. J Philos 88(12):693–708

    Google Scholar 

  26. Hintikka J (1962) Knowledge and belief: an introduction to the logic of the two notions. Cornell University Press

    Google Scholar 

  27. Hintikka J (2007) Socratic epistemology: explorations of knowledge-seeking by questioning. Cambridge University Press

    Google Scholar 

  28. Kelly TK (1996) The logic of reliable inquiry. Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  29. Lewis D (1969) Convention: a philosophical study. Harvard University Press

    Google Scholar 

  30. List C (2005) Group knowledge and group rationality: a judgment aggregation perspective. Episteme 2(01):25–38

    Article  Google Scholar 

  31. List C, Pettit P et al (2011) Group agency: the possibility, design, and status of corporate agents. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  32. Minică Ş (2008) Dynamic logic of questions. PhD Dissertation, PhD thesis, ILLC, University of Amsterdam

    Google Scholar 

  33. Olsson EJ, Westlund D (2006) On the role of the research agenda in epistemic change. Erkenntnis 65(2):165–183

    Article  Google Scholar 

  34. Quinton A (1975) The presidential address: social objects. In: Proceedings of the Aristotelian society, vol 76, pp 1–viii. JSTOR

    Google Scholar 

  35. Rolin K (2008) Science as collective knowledge. Cogn Syst Res 9(1):115–124

    Article  Google Scholar 

  36. Schaffer J (2005) Contrastive knowledge. Berl Stud Knowl Res 357

    Google Scholar 

  37. Schaffer J (2007) Knowing the answer. Philos Phenomenol Res 75(2):383–403

    Google Scholar 

  38. van Benthem J (2011) Logical dynamics of information and interaction. Cambridge University Press

    Google Scholar 

  39. van Benthem J, Minică Ş (2012) Toward a dynamic logic of questions. J Philos Log 41(4):633–669

    Google Scholar 

  40. van Ditmarsch H, van Der Hoek W, Kooi B (2007) Dynamic epistemic logic, vol 337. Springer Science & Business Media

    Google Scholar 

  41. Wegener A (2002) Die entstehung der kontinente, lecture held in 1912 for the general meeting of the geologische vereinigung in frankfurt. Translated by roland von huene as ’the origins of continents’ in 2002. Int J Earth Sci (Geol Rundsch) 91:S4–S17

    Google Scholar 

  42. Wisniewski A (1995) The posing of questions, logical foundations of erotetic inferences. Synthese Library. Kluwer

    Google Scholar 

  43. Wray KB (2007) Who has scientific knowledge? Soc Epistemol 21(3):337–347

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The contribution of Sonja Smets to this paper has received funding by the European Research Council under the European Community’s Seventh Framework Programme ERC Grant no. 283963. We also want to thank Johan van Benthem, Wes Holliday, Kevin Kelly, Christian List and Erik Olsson for illuminating discussions on topics related to this paper. Early versions of this work were presented at the 2nd workshop on Questions and Inquiry LoQI 2013; the workshop on Game Theory, Epistemic Logic and Related Topics 2013; LORI IV 2013; the KNAW Dependence Logic workshop 2014; the Symposium on Epistemic Logic and Formal Epistemology at the Pacific APA meeting 2014; Methods and Modality 2014; Esslli 2014 workshop on Epistemic Logic for Individual, Social, and Interactive Epistemology; 16th Szklarska Poreba workshop 2015 and the 2nd Belgrade graduate conference in philosophy and logic 2015. We thank the organizers of these workshops for the opportunity to present this work. In particular we thank Julia Staffel for the commentary presented on this work at the APA meeting in 2014. A closely related (though more intricate) framework (going beyond partitional questions and involving a number of additional testimonial knowledge conditions that increase the epistemic compatibility of a group) was presented in the third author’s ILLC Master thesis [9]. We thank the members of her thesis committee, Maria Aloni, Johan van Benthem, Branden Fitelson, Wesley Holliday, Robert van Rooij and Martin Stokhof, for their useful comments and feedback.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to A. Baltag .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

APPENDIX: Completeness and Decidability (Proofs)

APPENDIX: Completeness and Decidability (Proofs)

The proofs for Theorems 5.15.3 follow the standard method used in the completeness proof for epistemic logic with common knowledge and distributed knowledge, as introduced in [15]. The proofs’ plan is as follows:

  1. 1.

    Completeness for the Canonical Structure. First, we define a canonical structure. This is a Kripke structure, generated from the syntax in the usual way: possible worlds are maximally consistent theories. The canonical structure is not an interrogative epistemic model, since each modality has its own independent accessibility relation that cannot be reduced to a combination of the other relations. Nevertheless, our axioms are sound for this structure, and moreover they are complete: every maximal consistent theory satisfies itself.

  2. 2.

    Decidability via Finite Pseudo-Model Property. We use our version of a Fischer-Ladner closure to filtrate the canonical structure, obtaining a finite “pseudo-model”: this is a structure in which only the individual epistemic and issue modalities and the distributed-knowledge modality have their own independent accessibility relations \(\rightarrow _a\), \(\approx _a\), \(\rightarrow _{Dk}\) (with \(\rightarrow _{Dk}\subseteq \rightarrow _a\)), while the other modalities are defined exactly as in interrogative epistemic models. This gives us soundness and completeness of our logics with respect to finite pseudo-models, which implies the decidability of these logics.

  3. 3.

    Unraveling. In the third step, we unravel the pseudo-model obtained in the previous step: this means that we create all possible histories in the pseudo-model (all paths that can be taken when we follow these one-step relations \(\rightarrow _a\), \(\approx _a\), \(\rightarrow _{Dk}\)), thus forming a tree. Then we redefine the relations \(\rightarrow _a\) in order to ensure that they include the relation \(\rightarrow _{Dk}\); if necessary (for the introspective versions), we also close the relations \(\rightarrow _a\) and \(\approx _a\) under transitivity (or transitivity and symmetry). Finally, we take the interrogative epistemic model obtained in this way (in which all the other relations are defined as in any epistemic issue model). We define a bounded morphism from this model into the finite pseudo-model obtained in the previous step. Completeness for interrogative epistemic models follows immediately.

  4. 4.

    Completeness for the dynamic logics (proof of Theorem 5.3 ). In the last step we show that the dynamic logics can be reduced to their static counterparts, using the reduction axioms and a translation mechanism, which gives us completeness for these logics.

We now give a sketch of the main definitions and results in each step.

STEP 1: Soundness and Completeness for the Canonical Structure

The canonical structure for LGK is a Kripke structure

$$M = \left( S, \{\rightarrow _a: a\in G\}, \{\approx _a: a\in G\}, \rightarrow _{Dk}, \rightarrow _{Ck}, \rightarrow _{Gk}, \Vert \bullet \Vert \right) , \text{ where } $$
  • S consists of all maximally consistent sets of formulas (“theories”) of LGK;

  • \(s \rightarrow _a t \text { iff } \forall \varphi (K_a\varphi \in s \Rightarrow \varphi \in t)\);

  • \(s \approx _a t \text { iff } \forall \varphi (Q_a\varphi \in s \Rightarrow \varphi \in t)\);

  • \(s \rightarrow _{Dk} t \text { iff } \forall \varphi (Dk\varphi \in s \Rightarrow \varphi \in t)\);

  • \(s \rightarrow _{Ck} t \text { iff } \forall \varphi (Ck\varphi \in s \Rightarrow \varphi \in t)\);

  • \(s \rightarrow _{Gk} t \text { iff } \forall \varphi (Gk\varphi \in s \Rightarrow \varphi \in t)\);

  • \(\Vert p\Vert = \{s \in S; p \in s\}\).

It is easy to see that all the relations are reflexive. When the Positive Introspection axioms of \(LGK^+\) are added, one can show that all the relations are transitive; and when the Negative Introspection axioms of \(LGK^{\pm }\) are added as well, then all the relations are equivalence relations. For LaGK (and its introspective variants), the canonical structure has to be enriched with another independent accessibility relation \(\rightarrow _a^G\), defined in a similar way to the others. The semantics is obvious: each modality is interpreted as the Kripke modality for its associated relation. Soundness and completeness with respect to the canonical structure are proved in the usual way, via the Truth LemmaFootnote 11: each theory \(t\in S\) satisfies a formula \(\varphi \) iff \(\varphi \in s\).

Step 2: Decidability via Finite Pseudo-Model Property

A pseudo-model for LGK is a Kripke structure \(M = ( S, \{\rightarrow _a: a\in G\}, \{\approx _a: a\in G\}, \rightarrow _{Dk})\), satisfying the following conditions: all relations are reflexive; \(\rightarrow _a\approx _a\subseteq \rightarrow _a\); and \(\rightarrow _{Dk}\subseteq \rightarrow _a\). A pseudo-model for \(LGK^+\) is a pseudo-model for LGK in which all the relations are transitive. A pseudo-model for \(LGK^{\pm }\) is a pseudo-model for LGK in which all the relations are equivalence relations.

Given a pseudo-model M, the semantics of our basic language is given by interpreting the modalities \(K_a, Q_a\) and Dk as Kripke modalities for the corresponding relations, and defining the modalities Ck and Dk in the same way as on interrogative epistemic models.

For the language LaGK, we also define the modality \(K_a^G\) in the same way as on interrogative epistemic models (using the appropriate definitions for each of the logics LaGK, \(LaGK^+\), \(LaGK^{\pm }\)).

It is easy to see that each of these logics is sound with respect to the (corresponding) class of pseudo-models.

Let now M be the canonical structure constructed in Step 1, let \(\varphi \) be a consistent formula, and let \(s_{\varphi }\) be a maximally consistent theory that contains \(\varphi \). The Fisher-Ladner closure of \(\varphi \) is the smallest set of formulas \(\Sigma _{\varphi }\) satisfying the following conditions: \(\varphi \in \Sigma _{\varphi }\); \(\Sigma _{\varphi }\) is closed under subformulas; \(\Sigma _{\varphi }\) is closed under single negations (i.e. if \(\psi \in \Sigma _{\varphi }\) is not of the form \(\lnot \theta \), then \(\lnot \psi \in \Sigma _{\varphi }\)); if \(K_a\psi \in \Sigma _{\varphi }\) then \(Dk\psi \in \Sigma _{\varphi }\); if \(K_a\psi \in \Sigma _{\varphi }\) and \(\psi \) is not of the form \(Q_a\theta \), then \(K_a Q_a\psi \in \Sigma _{\varphi }\); if \(Ck\psi \in \Sigma _{\varphi }\) then \(\bigwedge _{a\in G} K_a Ck \psi \in \Sigma _{\varphi }\); finally, if \(Gk\psi \in \Sigma _{\varphi }\) then \(\bigwedge _{a\in G} Dk Q_a Gk \psi \in \Sigma _{\varphi }\). For LaGK, we need to add another closure requirement: \(K_a^G\psi \in \Sigma _{\varphi }\) implies \(Dk Q_a K_a^G \psi \in \Sigma _{\varphi }\).

It is easy to see that the Fisher-Ladner closure of \(\varphi \) is always finite.

We define an equivalence relation on the set S of all maximally consistent theories in the canonical structure M above, by putting:

$$s\cong _{\varphi } t \text{ iff } s\cap \Sigma _{\varphi }=t\cap \Sigma _{\varphi }.$$

We can now define a filtration \(M^f = \left( S^f, \{\rightarrow _a^f: a\in G\}, \{\approx _a^f: a\in G\}, \rightarrow _{Dk}^f,\right. \left. \rightarrow _{Ck}^f, \rightarrow _{Gk}^f, \Vert \bullet \Vert ^f\right) \) of the canonical structure M above, by putting:

  • \(S^f = \{[s]: s\in S\}\), where [s] is the equivalence class of s modulo \(\cong _{\varphi }\);

  • \([s]\rightarrow _a^f [t]\) if and only if \(\forall K_a\psi \in \Sigma _{\varphi } (K_a\psi \in s \Rightarrow \psi \in t)\); for \(LGK^+\), we use instead a transitive version: \([s]\rightarrow _a^f [t]\) if and only if \(\forall K_a\psi \in \Sigma _{\varphi } (K_a\psi \in s \Rightarrow K_a \psi \in t)\); while for \(LGK^{\pm }\), we use a transitive and symmetric version: \([s]\rightarrow _a^f [t]\) if and only if \(\forall K_a\psi \in \Sigma _{\varphi } (K_a\psi \in s \Leftrightarrow K_a \psi \in t)\);

  • \([s]\rightarrow _{Dk}^f [t]\) if and only if \(\forall Dk\psi \in \Sigma _{\varphi } (Dk\psi \in s \Rightarrow \psi \in t)\); again, we use the corresponding transitive version for \(LGK^+\), and the transitive and symmetric version for \(LGK^{\pm }\);

  • \([s]\approx _a^f [t]\) if and only if \(\forall Q_a\psi \in \Sigma _{\varphi } (Q_a\psi \in s \Leftrightarrow Q_a \psi \in t)\);

  • \(\rightarrow _{Ck}^f= (\bigcup _{a\in G} \rightarrow _a^f)^+\);

  • \(\rightarrow _{Gk}^f = (\bigcup _{a\in G} \rightarrow _{Dk}^f\approx _a^f)^+\);

  • for LaGK, \(LaGK^+\), \(LaGK^{\pm }\), we add the appropriately filtrated version for \(\rightarrow _a^{G}\);

  • \(\Vert p\Vert =\{[s]: s\in \Vert p\Vert _M\}=[\{[s]: p\in s\}\), for \(p\in \Phi \cap \Sigma \), and \(\Vert p\Vert =\emptyset \) for \(p\in \Phi \setminus \Sigma \).

It is now easy to check that \(M^f\) is a finite pseudo-model, and that it is indeed a filtration Footnote 12 of the canonical Kripke structure M.

By the usual properties of filtration, it follows that, for all formulas \(\psi \in \Sigma _{\varphi }\), we have:

$$[s]\models _{M^f} \psi \,\, \text{ iff } \,\, s \models _M \psi \,\, \text{ iff } \,\, \psi \in s.$$

Hence, \(\varphi \) is satisfied at state \([s_{\varphi }]\) in \(M^f\).

This gives us completeness with respect to finite pseudo-models, and thus decidability.

Step 3: Unraveling

Let \(\varphi , s_{\varphi }, \Sigma _{\varphi }\) be as above, and \(M^f\) be the finite pseudo-model constructed in Step 2. A history in \(M^f\) (with origin \([s_{\varphi }]\)) is any finite sequence \(h := ([s_0], R_0, [s_1],\dots ,R_{n-1}, [s_n])\) such that

  • for all \(k\le n: [s_k] \in S^f\);

  • \([s_0] = [s_{\varphi }]\);

  • for all \(k< n: R_k\in \{\rightarrow _a^f : a\in G\}\cup \{\approx _a^f : a\in G\}\cup \{\rightarrow _{Dk}^f\}\);

  • for all \(k< n: [s_k] R_k [s_{k+1}]\).

For any history \(h := ([s_0], R_0, [s_1],\dots ,R_{n-1}, [s_n])\), we write \(last(h)=[s_n]\).

The unraveling of \(M^f\) around \([s_{\varphi }]\) is a tree-structure \(\vec {M} = (\vec {S}, R_{\rightarrow _a}, R_{\approx _a}, R_{\rightarrow _{Dk}})\) such that

  • \(\vec {S} = \{h; h \text { history in } M^f \}\);

  • \(h R_{\rightarrow _a} h' \text { iff } h'= (h, \rightarrow _a^f, [s'])\) for some \(s'\);

  • \(h R_{\approx _a} h' \text { iff } h'= (h, \approx _a^f, [s'])\) for some \(s'\);

  • \(h R_{\rightarrow _{Dk}} h' \text { iff } h'= (h, \rightarrow _{Dk}^f, [s'])\) for some \(s'\).

We now convert \(\vec {M}\) into an interrogative epistemic model \(\vec {M} = (\vec {S}, \rightarrow , \approx , \Vert \bullet \Vert )\) as follows:

  • we put \(\approx _a:= (R_{\approx _a}\cup R_{\approx _a}^{-1})^*\), i.e. the least equivalence relation that includes \(R_{\approx _a}\);

  • for LGK, we take \(\rightarrow _a := \approx _a\cup (R_{\rightarrow _a}\approx _a) \cup (R_{\rightarrow _{Dk}}\approx _a)\); for \(LGK^+\), we take \(\rightarrow _a := (\approx _a\cup R_{\rightarrow _a}\cup R_{\rightarrow _{Dk}})^*\); and for \(LGK^{\pm }\), we put \(\rightarrow _a := (\approx _a\cup R_{\rightarrow _a}\cup R_{\rightarrow _a}^{-1}\cup R_{\rightarrow _{Dk}}\cup R_{\rightarrow _{Dk}}^{-1})^*\), i.e. the least equivalence relation that includes \(R_{\approx _a}\cup R_{\rightarrow _a}\cup R_{\rightarrow _{Dk}}\).

  • \(\Vert p\Vert =\{h\in \vec {S}: last(h)\in \Vert p\Vert _{M^f}\}\).

It is easy now to check that the map \(last: \vec {S}\rightarrow S^f\), which maps each history \(h\in \vec {S}\) into its last element \(last(h)\in S^f\), is a bounded morphism Footnote 13 between pseudo-models \(M^f\) and \(\vec {M}\). Since bounded morphisms preserve the truth of modal formulas, it follows that our consistent formula \(\psi \) is satisfied at history \(([s_{\varphi }])\) in the interrogative epistemic model \(\vec {M}\). This finishes our completeness proof for the static logics (Theorems 5.1 and 5.2).

Step 4: Completeness for the dynamic logics

We now prove Theorem 5.3. It is easy to see that the Reduction Axioms are sound. For completeness, we show that there exists a translation function t from formulas of our dynamic languages to formulas in the corresponding static languages, defined recursively as follows: \(t(p)=t([!]p):=p\); \(t(\lnot \varphi ):= \lnot t(\varphi )\); \(t(\varphi \wedge \psi ):= t(\varphi ) \wedge t(\psi )\); \(t(\Delta \varphi ):=\Delta t(\varphi )\) for all operators \(\Delta \in \{K_a, Q_a, Dk, Ck, Gk, K_a^G\}\); \(t([!]\lnot \varphi ):= t(\lnot [!]\varphi )\); \(t([!] (\varphi \wedge \psi )):= t([!]\varphi ) \wedge t([!]\psi )\); \(t([!] K_a\varphi )= t([!] K_a^G \varphi ):= t(K_a^G [!] \varphi )\); \(t([!] Dk \varphi ):= t(Dk [!]\varphi )\); \(t([!] Ck \varphi )=t([!] Gk \varphi ):=Gk t([!]\varphi )\).

Now we can show that, for every formula \(\varphi \) of our dynamic languages LGK! and LaGK!, we have:

  • \(t(\varphi )\) is a formula in the corresponding static language (LGK or LaGK);

  • the formula \(\varphi \Leftrightarrow t(\varphi )\) is a theorem in the corresponding dynamic logic LGK! or LaGK!.

The proof is by induction, using the Reduction Axioms. This result immediately implies Theorem 5.3.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Baltag, A., Boddy, R., Smets, S. (2018). Group Knowledge in Interrogative Epistemology. In: van Ditmarsch, H., Sandu, G. (eds) Jaakko Hintikka on Knowledge and Game-Theoretical Semantics. Outstanding Contributions to Logic, vol 12. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-62864-6_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics