Skip to main content

What Are Human Beings (That You Are Mindful of Them)? Notes from Neo-Darwinsim and Neo-Aristotelianism

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Issues in Science and Theology: Are We Special?

Abstract

The task of ascertaining whether and how human beings are unique presupposes that we know what human beings are: if we cannot identify human beings, we are unable to compare them against non-human beings. Traditionally, the answer to the question of what things are refers to their essences. However, for many decades since the 1950s, there has been a pervasive scepticism that any such essences exist, certainly for biological kinds, if not more broadly. Recently, there have been attempts to salvage biological essentialism, both by philosophers of biology and by neo-scholastic metaphysicians. In this paper, I argue that these attempts to defend biological essentialism are insufficient for the purposes of getting the quest for human uniqueness off the ground. From a theological standpoint, ‘human being’ should not be conflated with ‘Homo sapiens’.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 89.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    As we shall see, definitional work often involves empirical investigation: that is, the distinction between knowing what something is and knowing what it is like is not a hard one. The movement between definition and description is iterative.

  2. 2.

    The details of this story are currently under debate, but this need not detain us. Those interested may consult Amundson (2005), Atran (1990), Wilkins (2009), and Windsor (2003, 2006)

  3. 3.

    Ghiselin (1974) and Hull (1978) seem to think that individualism defeats biological essentialism tout court, and not just essentialism about biological kinds. I cannot see why this is so: after all, individuals can have essences.

  4. 4.

    To clarify, it is possible to be sceptical about some taxa, and not others. As we are most interested in Homo sapiens, we are most concerned with whether or not biological species form natural kinds. A nominalist about biological species might well be a realist about higher order taxa; she could certainly also be a realist about the distinction between living and non-living things.

  5. 5.

    This is not to deny that the kind vs individual debate is an important and interesting one. For example, on the view that we need natural kinds to have laws of nature, the individualist view excludes species from being subjects of such laws (e.g. Lowe 2006). We might additionally want Homo sapiens to be subject to laws of nature, but that is a separate issue from the one currently under consideration.

  6. 6.

    As we shall see later, neo-scholastic metaphysicians object to this characterization of essences as properties (Boulter 2013; Feser, 2014; Oderberg 2007).

  7. 7.

    This story appears in Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers, Book VI.20.

  8. 8.

    By ‘rational’, Aristotle and his inheritors do not mean ‘reasonable’, if that just refers to a particular cognitive style. The common accusation against Aristotle’s definition, that it leaves out the intellectually disabled, is misguided by this errant conflation of a trait and the essence from which it flows. We shall return to this point later in considering neo-scholastic positions.

  9. 9.

    See also Boulter (2012); Wilson et al. (2007).

  10. 10.

    Oderberg (2007) makes this point in drawing the distinction between epistemological and ontological vagueness; he correctly notes that essentialism can only accept the former but not the latter.

  11. 11.

    A comparison with music notes and colour categories might be useful here. There is not just one way to carve up sound wave frequencies and their corresponding pitches into pitch classes: different scales contain different numbers of pitch classes. Colour categorization seems to be more (but not entirely) psychologically universal, but even here, it is likely a contingent fact about how our eyes (e.g., rods, cones) and visual cortices (e.g., extended V4) work that determine how we categorize colours. There is, in other words, nothing special and objective – independent of us – about electromagnetic radiation with the wavelengths (approximately) 740nm and 625nm, such that they are objective boundaries. To most human beings under appropriate lighting conditions, these frequencies mark out the colour red, but that tells us more about human colour perception than about whether or not there is an objectively correct way to divide up a continuous colour spectrum into colour categories.

  12. 12.

    Oderberg (2007) tries to recruit the reality of intermediate or transitional species for the cause of essentialism, and he would be right in saying that if there were such species then ‘there must be determinate [species] relative to which the indeterminacy is measured’. There are, however, so many intermediate species; there just seems to be us, observing as we do only extant biodiversity directly, and extinct biodiversity in patches only.

  13. 13.

    As far as I know, only Devitt (2008: 374-375) explicitly deals with such cases, in his discussion of arbitrariness and anagenesis. He writes ‘Clearly, there would be a deal of arbitrariness about this choice. But we should not exaggerate how much’. It is not at all clear to me how he quantifies the amount of arbitrariness involved here.

  14. 14.

    Proponents of this theory take issue with characterizing it as a saltationist view, but this seems to be a protest against mischaracterizations by creationists and intelligent design theorists. The theory of punctuated equilibrium is a saltationist view in that it is not a gradualist one.

  15. 15.

    Both Eldredge (1985) and Ghiselin (1987) also consider the theory of punctuated equilibrium and the view of species as spatio-temporally bounded individuals as mutually reinforcing. For them, the periods of rapid change are where individual species begin and end. A similar view may also be found in Hull (1978).

  16. 16.

    As I have mentioned earlier, however, Devitt is likely to disagree with me on this. I have not been able to adjudicate the disagreement (see footnote 6).

  17. 17.

    Mayden (1997) distinguishes between these, and also describes three phylogenetic species concepts. These differences are not significant for our purposes.

  18. 18.

    This provides a response to my charge of arbitrariness: we are not the prototypical H. sapiens, just the most recent in the lineage.

  19. 19.

    This is reminiscent of Feser’s (2014) arguments, above. This is no coincidence, as Feser credits Oderberg as a major influence.

Bibliography

  • Amundson, R. (2005). The changing rule of the embryo in evolutionary biology: Structure and synthesis. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arsuaga, J. L. (2010). Terrestrial apes and phylogenetic trees. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 107(2), 8910–8917.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Atran, S. (1990). The cognitive foundations of natural history. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beebee, H. (2013). How to carve across the joint in nature without Abandoning Kripke-Putnam Semantics. In S. Mumford & M. Tugby (Eds.), Metaphysics and science (pp. 141–163). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boulter, S. J. (2012). Can evolutionary biology do without Aristotelian Essentialism? Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement, 70, 83–103.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boulter, S. J. (2013). Metaphysics from a biological point of view. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. (1999). Homeostasis, species, and higher taxa. In R. Wilson (Ed.), Species: New interdisciplinary studies (pp. 141–185). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Devitt, M. (2008). Resurrecting biological essentialism. Philosophy of Science, 75, 344–382.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dobzhansky, T. (1944). On species and races of living and fossil man. American Journal of Physical Anthropology, 2, 251–265.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dumsday, T. (2012). A new argument for intrinsic biological essentialism. The Philosophical Quarterly, 62, 486–504.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dupré, J. (1981). Natural kinds and biological taxa. The Philosophical Review, 90, 66–90.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elder, C. L. (2008). Biological species are natural kinds. The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 46, 339–362.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eldredge, N. (1985). Unfinished synthesis: Biological hierarchies and modern evolutionary thought. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eldredge, N., & Cracraft, J. (1980). Phylogenetic patterns and the evolutionary process: Method and theory in comparative biology. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eldredge, N., & Gould, S. J. (1972). Punctuated equilibria: An alternative to phyletic gradualism. In T. J. M. Schopf (Ed.), Models in paleobiology (pp. 82–115). San Francisco: Freeman Cooper.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feser, E. (2014). Scholastic metaphysics: A contemporary introduction. Heusenstamm: Editions Scholasticae.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ghiselin, M. T. (1974). A radical solution to the species problem. Systematic Biology, 23, 536–544.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ghiselin, M. T. (1987). Species are individuals: Therefore human nature is a metaphysical delusion. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 10, 77–78.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glock, H. J. (2012). The anthropological difference: What can philosophers do to identify the differences between human and non-human animals? Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement, 70, 105–131.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, P. E. (1999). Squaring the circle: Natural kinds with historical essences. In R. Wilson (Ed.), Species: New interdisciplinary studies (pp. 209–228). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawks, J. (2013). Significance of neanderthal and denisovan genomes in human evolution. Annual Review of Anthropology, 42, 433–449.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hawks, J. (2016, February 8). Human evolution is more a muddy delta than a branching tree. Aeon. Retrieved from: https://aeon.co/ideas/human-evolution-is-more-a-muddy-delta-than-a-branching-tree.

  • Hawks, J., & Cochran, G. (2006). Dynamics of adaptive introgression from archaic to modern humans. PaleoAnthropology, 2006, 101–115.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hull, D. L. (1965). The effect of essentialism on taxonomy – Two thousand years of stasis I. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 15, 314–326.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hull, D. L. (1976). Are species really individuals? Systematic Zoology, 25, 174–191.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hull, D. (1978). A matter of individuality. Philosophy of Science, 45, 335–360.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Isaac, N. J., Mallet, J., & Mace, G. M. (2004). Taxonomic inflation: Its influence on macroecology and conservation. Trends in Ecology & Evolution, 19, 464–469.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (1980). Naming and necessity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lowe, E. J. (2006). The four-category ontology: A metaphysical foundation for natural science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maclaurin, J., & Sterelny, K. (2008). What is biodiversity? Chicago: University Of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mayden, R. L. (1997). A hierarchy of species concepts: The denouement in the saga of the species problem. In M. F. Claridge, H. A. Dawah, & M. R. Wilson (Eds.), Species: The units of diversity (pp. 381–423). London: Chapman and Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, E. (1950). Taxonomic categories in Fossil Hominids. In M. Demerec (Ed.), Cold spring harbor symposia on quantitative biology (Vol. 15, pp. 109–118). Long Island: Long Island Biological Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, E. (1959). Typological versus population thinking. In B. J. Eggers (Ed.), Evolution and anthropology: A centennial appraisal (pp. 409–412). Washington, DC: The Anthropological Society of Washington.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mumford, S. (2005). Kinds, essences, powers. Ratio, 18, 420–436.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oderberg, D. S. (2007). Real essentialism. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oderberg, D. S. (2011). Essence and properties. Erkenntnis, 75, 85–111.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Okasha, S. (2002). Darwinian metaphysics: Species and the question of essentialism. Synthese, 131, 191–213.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Patterson, N., Richter, D. J., Gnerre, S., Lander, E. S., & Reich, D. (2006). Genetic evidence for complex speciation of humans and chimpanzees. Nature, 441, 1103–1108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R. (1945). The open society and its enemies, The spell of Plato (Vol. 1). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1970). Is semantics possible? Metaphilosophy, 1, 187–201.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1975). The meaning of meaning. In K. Gunderson (Ed.), Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science (Vol. VII, pp. 131–193). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. (1951). Two dogmas of empiricism. The Philosophical Review, 60, 20–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. (1966). Three grades of modal involvement. In W. V. Quine (Ed.), The ways of paradox and other essays. (Revised and Enlarged Edition) (pp. 156–174). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ridley, M. (1989). The cladistic solution to the species problem. Biology and Philosophy, 4, 1–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sangster, G. (2009). Increasing numbers of bird species result from taxonomic progress, not taxonomic inflation. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B: Biological Sciences, 276, 3185–3191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (1980). Evolution, population thinking, and essentialism. Philosophy of Science, 47, 350–383.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walsh, D. (2006). Evolutionary essentialism. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 57, 425–448.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilkerson, T. E. (1995). Natural kinds. Brookfield: Avebury.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilkins, J. S. (2009). Species: A history of the idea. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilkins, J. S. (2010). What is a species? Essences and generation. Theory in Biosciences, 129, 141–148.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, R. A., Barker, M. J., & Brigandt, I. (2007). When traditional essentialism fails: Biological natural kinds. Philosophical Topics, 35, 189–215.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Windsor, M. P. (2003). Non-essentialist methods in pre-darwinian taxonomy. Biology and Philosophy, 18, 387–400.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Windsor, M. P. (2006). The creation of the essentialism story: An exercise in metahistory. History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences, 28, 149–174.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zachos, F. E. (2015). Taxonomic inflation, the phylogenetic species concept and lineages in the tree of life – A cautionary comment on species splitting. Journal of Zoological Systematics and Evolutionary Research, 53, 180–184.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jonathan Jong .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Jong, J. (2017). What Are Human Beings (That You Are Mindful of Them)? Notes from Neo-Darwinsim and Neo-Aristotelianism. In: Fuller, M., Evers, D., Runehov, A., Sæther, KW. (eds) Issues in Science and Theology: Are We Special?. Issues in Science and Religion: Publications of the European Society for the Study of Science and Theology, vol 4. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-62124-1_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics