Skip to main content

The Dubious Moral Supervenience Thesis

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Supervenience and Normativity

Part of the book series: Law and Philosophy Library ((LAPS,volume 120))

Abstract

Non-reductionist moral realist views are supposed to have trouble explaining the truth of the moral supervenience thesis. In this paper I argue that the non-reductionist has nothing to worry about on this front. The positive case for the global moral supervenience thesis is flawed. I identify three considerations commonly cited in support of the thesis: the grounding concern, the horrendous deeds concern, and the normative authority concern. I argue that each one is based on mistakes, dubious assumptions and/or a question begging assumption of meta-ethical reductionism. I go on to argue that given reliable epistemic access to moral reality (something most moral realists will want to grant), the differential considered moral judgements of competent moral judges at different times and in different places is prima facie evidence that the moral landscape, like the physical landscape, is not uniform across time and space. This is incompatible with the local (non-trivial) moral supervenience thesis, according to which the subvening base excludes spatio-temporal location, thus fixing moral properties across time and space. I then argue that if the local (non-trivial) moral supervenience thesis is false there is no reason to think the global moral supervenience thesis is true. I conclude that short of a prior commitment to reductionism there is no good reason to think the global moral supervenience thesis is true.

I would like to thank the participants at the GRIN workshop on Supervenience and Normativity held at the University of Montreal in March 2014, with a special thanks to Carla Bognoli, Daniel Laurier, Brian McLaughlin and Antonino Rotolo. I would also like to thank Bartosz Brożek and Antonino Rotolo for inviting me to write this piece, and Julia K. Tanner who read and commented on an earlier draft.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    See also my 2013 article, although the case I make there is different from the one I will be making here (Harrison 2013).

  2. 2.

    See Kane (2003) for a more detailed description if a case of this kind.

  3. 3.

    I am speaking of moral valences as having causal powers. Some may object on the ground that there cannot be causation by supervenient properties. I see no good reason to hold such a view and some others agree (see for Shafer-Landau 2012, esp. pp. 27–29). But anyway, note that the moral valences are producing the overall action’s moral property of rightness or wrongness (or permissibility) and so we do not have causation across different metaphysical kinds (not that I consider there to be any problem even if we did, but I know that some do).

  4. 4.

    I am assuming the coherence of indeterminsitic causation, of course. Realist accounts of causation take the causal relation to be basic and maintain that one event causes another just in case the relation of causation obtains between them. On this kind of view there is nothing unintelligible in the idea of indeterministic causation. Causation just is the obtaining of a causal relation, and it can be indeterministic whether A will cause B, for it can be indeterministic whether this causal relation will obtain. If it does, then its obtaining just is A’s causing of B. One might reject realist accounts in favour of Reductionist accounts of causation that seek to analyse causation in terms of constant conjunction or counterfactual dependence, or the modalities of necessity and sufficiency. But these accounts have some serious problems and strike many, myself included, as fundamentally misguided insofar as it seems more natural to understand counterfactual dependence in terms of the existence of causal relations rather than the other way around (on this see Bigelow and Pargetter 1990).

  5. 5.

    I should add that though the moral supervenience thesis is compatible with moral particularism, it does seem to me to be against the spirit of moral particularism to defend it. For the moral particularist makes it his/her business to challenge the idea that the moral valence of a natural feature – or bundle of natural features – is invariant. But a moral particularist who affirms the moral supervenience thesis has to claim that the moral valence of a natural feature is invariant across naturalistically identical situations. That is a form of invariantism too.

  6. 6.

    The term ‘internalism’ should be understood here to refer to existence internalism and not judgement internalism.

  7. 7.

    It might be objected that there are some motivations found necessarily in all agents. Moral norms just are those norms of practical reason that we all, qua agents, have reason to do/refrain from doing (see Rosati 2003). It is contentious whether there are motivations that all agents necessarily have (see Joyce 2006, pp. 196–199). But even in the event that there are motivations that we must all, qua agents, possess, and that these give rise to norms of practical reason that accord with our pre-theoretical moral judgements (again, questionable) it remains doubtful this will provide what is needed. There is no space to elaborate, but in common with other moral realists I find constitutivist views of normativity unpersuasive (see Enoch 2006).

  8. 8.

    This point is, I think, more significant than it at first appears. As already noted, it is standardly seen as a virtue of reductionist views that they can explain the moral supervenience thesis (whereas non-reductionists cannot). However, the supervenience thesis in question cannot be one that includes under the umbrella of natural properties an act’s time and place. For as just noted, that version of the moral supervenience is trivially true and nobody has any difficulty explaining it. So, the version of the moral supervenience thesis that the reductionist can supposedly explain is the rather narrower, but substantial one that does not include temporal or spatial properties. Yet what justifies the exclusion of such properties? Reductionism in and of itself does not explain. Perhaps the reductionist could appeal to the fact our best normative moral theories do not allow time or place to make a difference. But our best normative moral theories are those that achieve the best fit with our considered moral intuitions. The evidence – I am going to suggest – is that these have altered over time. To discount the moral intuitions of competent moral judges from a previous time is to insist that time and place are morally irrelevant, rather than to show them to be.

  9. 9.

    A commitment to moral truths does not entail the epistemological commitment, but without it moral realism is unattractive. As Enoch puts it:

    If the best way out {in response to one version of the argument from disagreement] for the realist is to concede that moral beliefs – hers included, of course – do not reflect the moral facts, then she may perhaps have her realism, but only at the price of the most radical of skepticisms. A radically inaccessible realm of moral facts is, I think, a very small comfort for the realist. (2009, p. 22)

  10. 10.

    I borrow the term ‘faultless’ from Capps, Lynch and Massey (2009, p. 414). They too offer a faultless explanation, though one that is very different from mine.

References

  • Bigelow, J and Pargettter, R. 1990: “Metaphysics of causation,” Erkenntnis, 33, pp. 89–119

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blackburn, S. 1993: Essays in quasi-realism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. 1988: “How to be a moral realist,” in Essays on moral realism, ed. G. Sayre-McCord. Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brink, D.1989: Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Capps, D & Lynch, M & Massey, D 2009: “A coherent moral relativism.” Synthese, 166, pp. 413–430.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clarke, R. 2003: “Toward a credible agent-causal account of free will,” in Watson, G. (ed) Free Will. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coons, C. 2011: “How to prove that some acts are wrong (without using substantive moral premises).” Philosophical Studies, 155, no. 1, pp. 83–98

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dancy, J. 1993: Moral Reasons. Oxford: Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Dancy, J. 2000: “The particularist’s progress,” in Hooker, B and Little, M (eds.) Moral Particularism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwall, S. 1983: Impartial Reason. Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Doris, J. M., and Plakias, A. 2007.“How to Argue about Disagreement: Evaluative Diversity and Moral Realism.” In W. Sinnott-Armstrong (ed.), Moral Psychology, Volume 2: The Cognitive Science of Morality. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Enoch, D. 2006: “Agency, Shmagency: Why Normativity Won’t Come From What is Constitutive of Agency,” Philosophical Review. 115, pp. 169–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Enoch, D. 2009: “How is moral disagreement a problem for realism?” Ethics, 13, pp. 15–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harrison, G. 2013: “The moral supervenience thesis is not a conceptual truth” Analysis 73.1, pp. 62–68.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huemer, M. 2005: Ethical Intuitionism, Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Huemer, M. 2008: “Revisionary intuitionism,” Social Philosophy and Policy, 25 (1), pp. 368–392.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Joyce, R. 2001: The Myth of Morality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Joyce, R. 2006: The Evolution of Morality. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kane, R. 2003: “Responsibility, luck, and chance,” in Watson, G. (ed) Free Will. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard, C. 1996: The Sources of Normativity, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mackie, J.L. 1977:Ethics: Inventing right and wrong. Harmondsworth: Penguin

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. 1994: Mind and World. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McNaughton, D. and Rawling, P. and Lovibond, S. 2003: “Naturalism and Normativity,” Aristotelian Society Supplementary. Volume 77, 1, pp. 23–45.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murdoch, G.P. 1980: Theories of Illness: A World Survey. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ridge, M. 2007: “Anti-Reductionism and Supervenience,” Journal of Moral Philosophy, Vol. 4 (3), pp. 33–348.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosati, C. 2003: “Agency and the open question argument.” Ethics 113, pp. 490–527.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ross, S. 2012: “The Natural and the Normative: Supervenience and Counterfactuals,” The Philosophical Forum. pp. 197–2014

    Google Scholar 

  • Ross, W.D. [1930] 1988: The Right and the Good. Indianapolis, Ind.: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schiffer, S. 2003: The things we mean. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. 1980: “Minds Brains and Programs,” Behaviour and brain Sciences 3, pp. 417–424.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shafer-Landau, R. 1994: “Ethical disagreement, ethical objectivism and moral indeterminacy,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 54, pp. 331–344

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shafer-Landau, R. 2009: “A defence of categorical reasons.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society. Vol. CIX., part 2, pp. 189–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shafer-Landau, R. 2003: Moral Realism: A Defence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shafer-Landau 2012: “Evolutionary debunking, moral realism and moral knowledge,” Journal of ethics and social philosophy, vol. 7, no. 1.pp. 1–37

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, M. 1994: The Moral Problem. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tresan, J. 2010: “Question authority: in defence of moral naturalism without clout” Philosophical Studies 150, pp. 221–238.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Velleman, J. D. 2000: The possibility of practical reason. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vogelstein, E. 2013: “Moral normativity,” Philosophical Studies 165, pp. 1083–1095

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zangwill, N. 2005: “Moore, morality, supervenience, essence, epistemology,” American Philosophical Quarterly, 42, pp. 125–130.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Gerald K. Harrison .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Harrison, G.K. (2017). The Dubious Moral Supervenience Thesis. In: Brożek, B., Rotolo, A., Stelmach, J. (eds) Supervenience and Normativity. Law and Philosophy Library, vol 120. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-61046-7_5

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-61046-7_5

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-61045-0

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-61046-7

  • eBook Packages: Law and CriminologyLaw and Criminology (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics