Skip to main content

Explaining Behavior and Development in the Language of Psychology

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Problem Behavior Theory and the Social Context

Part of the book series: Advancing Responsible Adolescent Development ((ARAD))

  • 549 Accesses

Abstract

This paper has had as its aim the instigation of renewed attention to the doctrine of reductionism, especially in terms of its implications for the relationship of physiology and psychology. Despite the empirical character of the ultimate answer, it is asserted that the questions involved in the doctrine may properly be the concern of a logical analysis. After briefly sketching four propositions which constitute essential notions of reductionism, the argument focused upon the logical possibility of a complete translatability or derivability of the concepts and laws of psychology from those of physiology. The central contention was that the latter, lacking terms to describe the behavioral environment, was logically inadequate as a base for a thoroughgoing reduction of the former. The remainder of the paper commented upon the relationship of the doctrine to the idea of a hierarchical ordering of the sciences and to the possibility of achieving a unification of science.

Reprinted with permission from:

Jessor, R. (1958). The problem of reductionism in psychology. Psychological Review, 65(3), 170–178.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Sound empirical work, of course, requires no defense, whether motivated by reductionistic aims or not. Nothing said in this paper should be interpreted as depreciating the value of empirical or theoretical efforts to bridge the gap between disciplines.

  2. 2.

    Finer discriminations can, of course, easily be made by including the well-known “border” disciplines such as biochemistry or social psychology. But the fact that there is no sharp break between the sciences, and that it is frequently difficult to tell where one leaves off and the other begins, need not, in itself, challenge the autonomous existence of the several disciplines. What may be implied by ordering them in a hierarchy from lower to higher will be discussed shortly; for the moment it is only important to consider that this is one of the notions essential to the doctrine of reductionism.

  3. 3.

    Terms in this paper referring to “position” in the hierarchy of the sciences, e.g., higher-lower, upward-downward, top-bottom, are by no means to imply any valuative judgment. The meaning of position in the hierarchy has been variously specified, for example, as referring to levels of abstraction or levels of integration, or as referring to the order of historical evolution within the universe of the subject matter of the sciences, or even to the order of historical emergence of the sciences themselves (White, 1949). As pointed out later, the concept of levels of science is not an analytically clear one (cf. Kroeber, 1952). For present purposes it is sufficient to take note of the existence in scientific discourse of such a hierarchical concept, and to recognize the traditional general ordering which places the physical sciences at the base, the biological sciences in the middle, and the social sciences at the top of the hierarchy.

  4. 4.

    The writer assumes that the study of animal behavior by psychologists is merely propaedeutic to a science of human behavior.

  5. 5.

    That is, the same psychological event may be served by (partly constituted of) an almost infinite variety of different physiological events.

  6. 6.

    To achieve such a derivation requires some law connecting the biological concepts with the physical concepts. “But those connecting laws are not purely physical in character” (Hempel, 1951, p. 321). And they have the character of empirical laws.

References

  • Bentley, A. F. (1941). The behavioral superfice. Psychological Review, 48, 39–59.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bergmann, G. (1953). Theoretical psychology. Annual Review of Psychology, 4, 435–458.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • von Bertalanffy, L. (1951). Problems of general systems theory. Human Biology, 23(4), 302–312.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Bertalanffy, L. (1952). Problems of life. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brunswik, E. (1939). The conceptual focus of some psychological systems. Journal of Unified Science, 8, 36–49.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brunswik, E. (1952). The conceptual framework of psychology, International encyclopedia of unified science (Vol. 1). Chicago: University of Chicago Press. (no. 10.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Brunswik, E. (1955). In defense of probabilistic functionalism: A reply. Psychological Review, 62(3), 236–242.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, D. T. (1954). Operational delineation of “what is learned” via the transposition experiment. Psychological Review, 61(3), 167–174.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, D. T. (1956). Adaptive behavior from random response. Behavioral Science, 1(2), 105–110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feigl, H. (1953). The mind-body problem in the development of logical empiricism. In H. Feigl & M. Brodbeck (Eds.), Readings in the philosophy of science (pp. 612–626). New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hebb, D. O. (1949). The organisation of behavior. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. G. (1951). General systems theory and the unity of science. Human Biology, 23(4), 313–322.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Jessor, R. (1956). Phenomenological personality theories and the data language of psychology. Psychological Review, 63(3), 173–180.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Kantor, J. R. (1942). Preface to interbehavioral psychology. Psychological Record, 5, 173–193.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kessen, W., & Kimble, G. A. (1952). “Dynamic systems” and theory construction. Psychological Review, 59(4), 263–267.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Krech, D. (1950). Dynamic systems, psychological fields, and hypothetical constructs. Psychological Review, 57(5), 283–290.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Kroeber, A. L. (1952). The nature of culture. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Littman, R. A., & Rosen, E. (1950). Molar and molecular. Psychological Review, 57(1), 58–65.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Meehl, P. E., & Sellars, W. (1956). The concept of emergence. In H. Feigl & M. Scriven (Eds.), The foundations of science and the concepts of psychology and psychoanalysis (pp. 239–252). Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rozeboom, W. W. (1956). Mediation variables in scientific theory. Psychological Review, 63(4), 249–264.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, W. (1956). Empiricism and the philosophy of mind. In H. Feigl & M. Scriven (Eds.), The foundations of science and the concepts of psychology and psychoanalysis (pp. 253–329). Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smedslund, J. (1953). The problem of “What is learned?”. Psychological Review, 60(3), 157–158.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Smedslund, J. (1955). Multiple-probability learning: An inquiry into the origins of perception. Oslo, NO: Akademisk Forlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tolman, E. C. (1949). Purposive behavior in animals and men. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • White, L. A. (1949). The science of culture: A study of man and civilization. New York: Farrar, Straus.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodger, J. H. (1952). Biology and language: An introduction to the methodology of the biological sciences including medicine. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodger, J. H. (1956). Physics, psychology, and medicine: A methodological essay. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Note

The author was a Social Science Research Council postdoctoral fellow at the University of California during the time in which this paper was prepared.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Richard Jessor .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Jessor, R. (2017). Explaining Behavior and Development in the Language of Psychology. In: Problem Behavior Theory and the Social Context . Advancing Responsible Adolescent Development. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-57885-9_12

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics