Skip to main content

On Time Order and Causal Order in the EPR Experiment

  • Conference paper
  • First Online:
Making it Formally Explicit

Part of the book series: European Studies in Philosophy of Science ((ESPS,volume 6))

  • 296 Accesses

Abstract

The aim of this paper is to discuss the rejection of the so-called Measurement Independence—i.e. No-conspiracy—condition, in the context of causal explanations of EPR correlations, and survey some of its implications. In particular, I pay attention here to a specific way Measurement Independence is violated. It has to do with two assumptions about the presupposed causal order and space-time arrangement of the events involved in the EPR picture. The consequences are mostly, and more importantly, related to locality issues.

Financial support is gratefully acknowledged from BBVA Foundation, research project “Causality, Locality and Free Will in Quantum Mechanics”, and Spanish Ministry of Economy, Industry and Competitiveness, project FFI2014-57064-P.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See, for instance, (Graßhoff et al. 2005) for a more recent example.

  2. 2.

    Reference to ‘free will’ in this context is usually set aside in favour of more general stronger claims about ‘world (or cosmic) conspiracies’ instead. The exact relation between the requirement of Measurement Independence, ‘free will’ and ‘world conspiracies’ will be addressed more in detail in what follows.

  3. 3.

    I would even say that it is indeed the fact that these assumptions behind the idea of free will carry over to Measurement Independence what it is most often seen as justifying that the later stands for the former. And my point in San Pedro (2013) is precisely that such assumptions are not well grounded and can all be challenged.

  4. 4.

    This is, by the way, where the origin of the terminology No-conspiracy can be traced back to.

  5. 5.

    This is indeed the view defended by Bas van Fraassen in his influential “Charybdis of Realism …” (van Fraassen 1982).

  6. 6.

    As we shall see in a moment, a violation of Causal Order will not mean that all causal influences propagate backwards in time but just that some do. This will be in fact the source of some criticism as regards common cause models featuring a violation of Causal Order.

  7. 7.

    However, rejecting Time Order would result in other different causal pictures (see causal models 2 and 3 below).

  8. 8.

    Classical references to retrocausal pictures include Sutherland (1983), de Beauregard (1987) or more recently Price (19941996). Huw Price, for instance, has gone as far as to argue that the characteristic time-symmetry of quantum mechanics (and of microphysics in particular) may imply, given some further assumptions about the ontology of the theory, the existence of backwards in time causation, or retrocausality, as he terms it (Price 2012).

  9. 9.

    I must thank a reviewer for hinting this further kind of difficulties.

  10. 10.

    Note that we cannot rule out this possibility completely just by looking at the other relevant probabilistic relations among O L and m L . In fact, we should expect them both to be correlated.

  11. 11.

    Obviously, this is not the only temporal arrangement possible. Time Order could be violated as well by altering the order between measurements and outcomes, and leaving the common cause in the past of both, just as it is standard. The problem with such a structure, of course, is that it is very difficult to think of outcomes taking palace (or being observed) before measurements have been performed.

  12. 12.

    This model, of course, needs to assume that there is some lapse of time—or rather some region of space-time—, however little this may be, between the performance of a measurement and the occurrence of the corresponding outcome. See San Pedro (2012) for details.

References

  • Bell, J. 1964. On the Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen paradox. Physics 1: 195–200. Reprinted in Bell 1987, pp. 14–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bell, J. 1987. Speakable and unspeakable in quantum mechanics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cushing, J., and E. McMullin, eds. 1989. Philosophical consequences of quantum theory. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Beauregard, O.C. 1987. On the zigzagging causality EPR model: Answer to Vigier and coworkers and to Sutherland. Foundations of Physics 17: 775–785.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Graßhoff, G., S. Portmann, and A. Wüthrich. 2005. Minimal assumption derivation of a Bell-type inequality. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 56: 663–680.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hofer-Szabó, G., M. Rédei, and L.E. Szabó. 2002. Common causes are not common-common causes. Philosophy of Science 69: 623–636.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Price, H. 1994. A neglected route to realism about quantum mechanics. Mind 103: 303–336.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Price, H. 1996. Time’s arrow and Archimedes’ point. New York/Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Price, H. 2012. Does time-symmetry imply retrocausality? How the quantum world says “maybe”? Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 43: 75–83.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rédei, M., and S. Summers. 2002. Local primitive causality and the common cause principle in quantum field theory. Foundations of Physics 32: 335–355.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach, H. 1956. The direction of time, ed. M. Reichenbach. Unabridged Dover, 1999 (republication of the original University of California Press 1956 publication).

    Google Scholar 

  • San Pedro, I. 2012. Causation, measurement relevance and no-conspiracy in EPR. European Journal for Philosophy of Science 2: 137–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • San Pedro, I. 2013. On free will and no-conspiracy. In New vistas on old problems: Recent approaches to the foundations of quantum mechanics, eds. T. Sauer and A. Wüthrich, 87–102. Berlin: Edition Open Access, Max Planck Research Library for the History and Development of Knowledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sutherland, R.I. 1983. Bells theorem and backwards-in-time causality. International Journal Theoretical Physics 22: 377–384.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B.C. 1982. The charybdis of realism: Epistemological implications of Bell’s inequality. Synthese 52: 25–38. Reprinted with corrections in (Cushing and Mcmullin, 1989, pp. 97–113).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Iñaki San Pedro .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this paper

Cite this paper

San Pedro, I. (2017). On Time Order and Causal Order in the EPR Experiment. In: Hofer-Szabó, G., Wroński, L. (eds) Making it Formally Explicit. European Studies in Philosophy of Science, vol 6. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-55486-0_8

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics