Skip to main content

Uncertainty and Economic Instability

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Uncertainty in Economics

Part of the book series: Contributions to Economics ((CE))

  • 1142 Accesses

Abstract

Uncertainty is a central topic in Keynes’ “General Theory of Employment, Interests and Money” (1936), but also his dissertation “A Treaties on Probability” (1921) empathises the importance of uncertainty in social systems. Here he argued that social life is aleatory and yet not random. This implies that social systems (of which the economy is part) cannot in general yield certainty because they are open and organic (Chick 2003; Chick and Dow 2005). This means that structures and interrelations evolve in such a way that the past is a very limited guide to the future (Lawson 1988; Dow 2002, 2003). Therefore, Keynes doubts that rational probability calculations are particularly helpful in the social realm. Keynes’ early rather philosophical thoughts on uncertainty strongly influenced his economics and became central to his legacy. Some, among them Skidelsky (2010: 83), have claimed that: “Uncertainty pervades Keynes’ picture of economic life. It explains why people hold savings in liquid forms, why investment is volatile, and why the rate of interest doesn’t adjust savings and investment. It also explains why economic progress throughout history has been so slow and fitful. All the actors in his (Keynes’) drama are motivated to a greater or less extent by uncertainty about the future, and regard the possession of money, or liquidity, as an important way of coping with it. Uncertainty breaks the tight link between supply and demand assumed by Say’s Law.”

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 99.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Say (1880: 138) had argued that demand necessarily equals supply: “A product is no sooner created, than it, from that instant, affords a market for other products to the full extent of its own value.” And continues: “As each of us can only purchase the productions of others with his own productions—as the value we can buy is equal to the value we can produce, the more men can produce, the more they will purchase.”

  2. 2.

    By the time, Keynes was working on his first drafts of his “A Treaties on Probability”, the topic of uncertainty also preoccupied Frank Knight and Friedrich A. von Hayek (Hutchison 2009).

  3. 3.

    There seems to be an inconsistency between Keynes’ theory of probability in “A Treaties on Probability” and his later economic writings. Some have argued, among them Bateman (1987, 1996), Davis (1994, 2003) and Gillies (2003), that Keynes changed his theory of probability later on in his life. In his “Treaties on Probability,” he initially stated with a logical account, but later, he would adopt Ramsey’s subjective account of probability. In what follows, I will initially focus on the logical concept of probability, which Keynes developed in his 1921 book.

  4. 4.

    Fundamental uncertainty is identical to ontological uncertainty. Keynes and Knight thus identified similar stages of knowledge.

  5. 5.

    E. g.: Keynes (1921: 1). “Part of our knowledge we obtain direct; and part by argument.”

  6. 6.

    Naturally, the second critique fails as soon as one introduces Subjective Bayesianism (or subjective probability theory). It assumes that individuals in circumstances of uncertainty have well-defined subjective probabilities. Thus, the numerical basis for rational choice theory is no longer missing. Decisions in the face of uncertainty become like choices involving risk. Decisions are based on a subjective rather than on an objective concept of probability. Consequently, modelling rational choice involving uncertainty did become unproblematic. Though the modelling issue seems to be solved today in the aftermath of expected utility theory (Savage 1954), the question remains whether people behave rationally.

  7. 7.

    E. g.: Dow (2010: 3): “By ‘probability’ Keynes meant logical probability, ‘the various degrees of rational belief about a proposition which different amounts of knowledge authorize us to entertain’. Quantified probability based on frequency distributions was a special case; the general case was uncertainty, where even non-quantifiable (ordinal) probability may not be identifiable.”

  8. 8.

    In a letter to Harrod, Keynes (1938) argued: “It seems to me that economics is a branch of logic, a way of thinking; and that you do not repel sufficiently firmly attempts a la Schultz to turn it into a pseudo-natural-science. One can make some quite worthwhile progress merely by using your axioms and maxims. But one cannot get very far except by devising new and improved models. This requires, as you say, “a vigilant observation of the actual working of our system”. Progress in economics consists almost entirely in a progressive improvement in the choice of models. The grave fault of the later classical school, exemplified by Pigou, has been to overwork a too simple or out of date model, and in not seeing that progress lay in improving the model; whilst Marshall often confused his models, for the devising of which [b] he had great genius, by wanting to be realistic and by being unnecessarily ashamed of lean and abstract outlines. […] Economics is a science of thinking in terms of models joined to the art of choosing models, which are relevant to the contemporary world. It is compelled to be this, because, unlike the typical natural science, the material to which it is applied is, in too many respects, not homogeneous through time. The object of a model is to segregate the semi-permanent or relatively constant factors from those which are transitory or fluctuating so as to develop a logical way of thinking about the latter, and of understanding the time sequences to which they give rise in particular cases. Good economists are scarce because the gift for using “vigilant observation” to choose good models, although it does not require a highly specialised intellectual technique, appears to be a very rare one. In the second place, as against Robbins, economics is essentially a moral science and not a natural science. That is to say, it employs introspection and judgments of value”. Harrod (1938) discusses Keynes concerns regarding the possibility of general laws in economics. For a complete reprint of the letter please, see http://economia.unipv.it/harrod/edition/editionstuff/rfh.346.htm (2014-07-03).

  9. 9.

    See also Minsky (2008: Chaps. VIII & IX).

  10. 10.

    Priddat and Koehn (2014), suggest that Keynes as a dandy himself, imagines a well educated statesman as the ideal decision maker.

References

  • Backhouse RE (2010) The puzzle of modern economics: science or ideology? Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bateman BW (1987) Keynes’ changing conception of probability. Econ Philos 3(1):97–119

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bateman BW (1996) Keynes’ uncertain revolution. University of Michigan Press, Ann Arbor

    Google Scholar 

  • Chick V (2003) Theory, method and mode of thought in Keynes’ General Theory. J Econ Methodol 10(3):307–327

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chick V, Dow SC (2005) The meaning of open systems. J Econ Methodol 12(3):363–381

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coddington A (1976) Keynesian economics: the search for first principles. J Econ Lit 14(4):1258–1273

    Google Scholar 

  • Coddington A (1982) Deficient foresight: a troublesome theme in keynesian economics. Am Econ Rev 72(3):480–487

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis J (1994) Keynes’ philosophical development. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Davis JB (2003) The relationship between Keynes’ early and later philosophical thinking. In: Runde J, Mizuhara S (eds) The philosophy of Keynes’ economics: probability, uncertainty and convention. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Dequech D (1999) Expectations and confidence under uncertainty. J Post Keynesian Econ 21(3):415–430

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dequech D (2000) Fundamental uncertainty and ambiguity. East Econ J 26(1):41–60

    Google Scholar 

  • Dequech D (2001) Bounded rationality, institutions, and uncertainty. J Econ Issues 35(4):911–929

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dequech D (2003a) Conventional and unconventional behavior under uncertainty. J Post Keynesian Econ 26(1):145–168

    Google Scholar 

  • Dequech D (2003b) Uncertainty and economic sociology: a preliminary discussion. Am J Econ Soc 62(3):509–532

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dequech D (2008) Neoclassical, mainstream, orthodox, and heterodox economics. J Post Keynesian Econ 30(2):279–302

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dow SC (2002) Economic methodology: an inquiry. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Dow SC (2003) Understanding the relationship between mathematics and economics. J Post Keynesian Econ 25(4):547–560

    Google Scholar 

  • Dow SC (2010) Keynes on knowledge, expectations and rationality. In: Phelps ES, Frydman R (eds) Microfoundations for modern macroeconomics. Princeton University Press, Princeton, pp 1–28

    Google Scholar 

  • Dow SC, Dow A (1985) Animal spirits and rationality. In: Lawson T (ed) Keynes’ economics: methodological issues. Croom Helm, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Gillies D (2003) Probability and uncertainty in Keynes’ the general theory. In: Runde J, Mizuhara S (eds) The philosophy of Keynes’ economics: probability, uncertainty and convention. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Harrod RF (1938) Scope and method of economics. Econ J 48(191):383–412

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harrod RF (1990) The life of John Maynard Keynes. Easton, Norwalk

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutchison TW (1978) On revolutions and progress in economic knowledge. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutchison TW (2009) A formative decade: methodological controversy in the 1930s. J Econ Methodol 16(3):297–314

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keynes JM (1921) A treatise on probability. Rough Draft Printers, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Keynes JM (1925) Am I a liberal? Essays in persuasion. W.W. Norton, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Keynes JM (1936) The general theory of employment, interest and money. Palgrave Macmillan, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Keynes JM (1937) The general theory of employment. Quart J Econ 52(3):209–223

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koppl R (1991) Retrospectives: animal spirits. J Econ Perspect 5(3):203–210

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lawson T (1983) Different approaches to economic modelling [On Keynesian model building and the rational expectations critique]. Camb J Econ 7(1):77–84. Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Lawson T (1985a) Uncertainty and economic analysis. Econ J 95(380):909–927

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lawson T (1985b) Keynes’ economics: methodological issues. Croom Helm, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Lawson T (1988) Probability and uncertainty in economic analysis. J Post Keynesian Econ 11(1):38–65

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levi I (1986) The paradoxes of Allais and Ellsberg. Econ Philos 2:23–53

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lucas RE (1972) Expectations and the neutrality of money. J Econ Theor 4:103–124

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machina M (1987) Choice under uncertainty: problems solved and unsolved. J Econ Perspect 1:121–154

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matthews RCO (1984) Animal spirits. Proc Br Acad 70:209–229

    Google Scholar 

  • McKenna EJ, Zannoni DC (2001) Post-Keynesian economics and nihilism. J Post Keynesian Econ 23:331–347

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meeks JG (1978) Bray on Keynes on scientific method. J Econ Stud 5(2)

    Google Scholar 

  • Minsky H (2008) John Maynard Keynes. McGraw-Hill, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Donnell RM (1982) Keynes: philosophy and economics, an approach to rationality and uncertainty. PhD Dissertation. University of Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Donnell RM (1989) Keynes: philosophy, economics and politics, the philosophical foundations of Keynes’ thought and their influence on his economics and politics. MacMillan, London

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Donnell RM (1990) The epistemology of J. M. Keynes. Br J Philos Sci 41:330–350

    Google Scholar 

  • Priddat BP, Koehn J (2014) Keynes war ein Liberaler. In: Pies I, Leschke M (Hrsg) J. M. Keynes Gesellschaft. Mohr Siebeck, Tübingen

    Google Scholar 

  • Savage L (1954) The foundations of statistics. Dover Publications, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Say JB (1880) A treatise on political economy or the production, distribution, and consumption of wealth. Batoche Books, Kitchener (This is an English translation of Say’s Traité d’economie politique, first published in 1803)

    Google Scholar 

  • Skidelsky R (2003) John Maynard Keynes. MacMillan, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Skidelsky R (2010) Keynes: the return of the master. Publicaffairs, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Weintraub RE (1975) ‘Uncertainty’ and the Keynesian revolution. Hist Polit Econ 7(4):530–548

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Köhn, J. (2017). Uncertainty and Economic Instability. In: Uncertainty in Economics. Contributions to Economics. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-55351-1_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics