Skip to main content

The Primacy of Training over Truth: From Rorty to Sloterdijk

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
  • 370 Accesses

Abstract

Richard Rorty was a radical pragmatist philosopher in many aspects; particularly in his anti-metaphysical point of views. However, when it comes to religion he, for several decades, used to adopt an orthodox, metaphysical atheist standpoint. This chapter explains his 2003 transition from that intellectual idea to abandoning atheism as an untenable metaphysical position and replacing it with anti-clericalism which is a political standpoint and more defensible for an anti-essentialist and neo-pragmatist philosopher. I will also suggest that the mentioned transition implies that the Jeffersonian compromise defined and defended by him is also problematic. The Jeffersonian compromise, for Rorty of pre-2003, was an American version of a democratic compromise between believers of different faiths and also non-believers i.e. one trades dropping ‘reference to religious beliefs in the public square’ to ‘religious liberty’. The chapter argues that this trade does not seem to be coherent with his transition to a more pragmatic anti-clerical standpoint. Moreover it shows the necessity of a new compromise. At this juncture, Peter Sloterdijk’s neo-Nietzscheian approach to ‘religions as anthropotechnic systems’ becomes relevant. The author puts forward a synthesis of Rorty and Sloterdijk’s approaches and calls it ‘the primacy of training over truth’.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    During his academic life Rorty (1931–2007) was in a constant process of negotiation with other philosophers and frequently revised his former intellectual positions following these encounters with his colleagues. This broad-mindedness and intellectual flexibility can be connected to his general pragmatist view-point. Pragmatism for Rorty had at least three meanings: firstly, anti-essentialism applied to ‘truth’, ‘morality’ and ‘knowledge’, secondly, the view that there is not any metaphysical difference between value and fact, and more relevant here, ‘the doctrine that there are no constraints on inquiry’ except ‘those retail constraints provided by the remarks of our fellow inquirers’ (Malachowski, 2002: pp. 83–4; cf. Rorty, 1982: pp. 162–5). Thus he was rejecting the age old correspondence theory of truth. For him ‘foundationalism’ in modern epistemology is closely related to that theory and he could not accept either of them (Malachowski, 1992: pp. 139–55; Guignon and Hiley, 1992: pp. 339–64). Rorty consequently believed that holding an idea as essentially and ‘objectively’ true is a form of ‘banging on the table’ (Rorty, 2015). One cannot possess a birds-eye neutral point of view to confirm that our mind images of reality are corresponding with it (hence objectivity). As a pragmatist, he also believed that there is not any significant difference in terms of consequences between these two statements: ‘it is true because it works’ and ‘it works because it is true’ (Van Niekerk, 2013: p. 302). So instead of asking about the truthfulness of a statement we should ask ‘whether there are new ways of describing and re-describing the world that better serve our variety of goals’ (Ryerson, 2006, p. 8). And as long as the conversation lasts we should hope for a new and more promising agreement and compromise. In this way, challenging one’s own standpoint was the indispensable part of his pragmatism, not merely a supplementary element (Malachowski, 2002, p. 67ff).

  2. 2.

    Rorty used Thomas Jefferson as a symbol of the Enlightenment privatisation of religion because of a quotation from him that says: ‘it does me no injury for my neighbour to say that there are twenty Gods or no God’ (Rorty, 2008: p. 175). But it is noteworthy that many philosophers, intellectuals and specifically the Enlightenment figures said more or less the same thing; and those are the people that deserve to take the credit for the principle of tolerance. Rorty, nonetheless, preferred a politician to be the symbol of the doctrine. It seems that in this way he wanted to remain loyal to his main post-philosophical/post-truth pragmatism. That is to say, it does not matter who talked about this principle and formulated it philosophically but the politician who practiced that doctrine and brought it to life should be the main figure. So Jefferson is more relevant than, say, John Stuart Mill who for the first time used the term in its modern sense (Forst, 2012).

  3. 3.

    Sloterdijk just like Rorty cannot be in more agreement with Nietzsche on his conception of truth. Nietzsche answering to the question of the quiddity of truth wrote:

    A mobile army of metaphors, metonymies, anthropomorphisms, in short a sum of human relations which became poetically and rhetorically intensified, metamorphosed, adorned, and after long usage seem to a nation fixed, canonic and binding […] to be truthful, that is, to use the usual metaphors. (Nietzsche, 1997: p. 92)

    That is to say, for Nietzsche, the weak have made up those metaphors to survive (Mendieta, 2012a: p. 65) but with the eclipse of God any reference to ‘substantive truth’ will be problematic (Hatab, 2008: p. 11). In the same vein, Sloterdijk does not invite us to engage with any sort of comprehensive doctrine. Conversely, in his first influential project, Critique of Cynical Reason (1987) he preferred a kynical resistance of Diogenes against the Platonic idealism. Diogenes refused the language of the philosopher not by a better or more philosophical language but by living against it through showing ‘contempt for fame’, ridiculing the architecture and refusing to respect (Sloterdijk, 1987: p. 103). Socrates wished to begin a conversation with Diogenes because he was the dominant master of refutation through dialogue. This was Diogenes, though, that never fall into the trap. For Sloterdijk, Diogenes’s kynical materialism was the ‘dirty materialism’ in which animalities challenges the public square to overcome the idealist arrogance (Sloterdijk, 1987: p. 105).

  4. 4.

    Sloterdijk’s original term is überhumanismus.

  5. 5.

    We should recall that Sloterdijk believes that religions do not exist. What exist is only anthropotechnic systems.

  6. 6.

    In response, Lafonte hesitates over the possibility of translation of the religious vocabulary into secular language. She convincingly argues that: ‘translation presupposes that it is possible to come to the same results by different epistemic means’ (Lafonte, 2013: p. 237 – ital. Original). Nonetheless this presupposition is very problematic. Moreover, if the translation is possible only in a few cases of overlapping between the secular and non-secular proposals, then the very process of translation becomes unnecessary.

References

  • Audi, R. (1997). Liberal Democracy and the Place of Religion. In R. Audi & N. Wolterstroff, Politics in Religion in the Public Square (pp. 1–66). London: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beck, U. (2002). Risk Society: Toward A New Modernity. London: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernstein, R. (2010). The Pragmatic Turn. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Calhoun, C. (2011). Secularism, Citizenship, and the Public Sphere. In C. Calhoun, M. Juergensmeyer, & J. VanAntwerpen, Rethinking Secularism (pp. 75–91). Oxford, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Casanova, J. (2013). Exploring the Postsecular. In C. Calhoun, E. Mendieta, & J. VanAntwerpen, Habermas and Religion (pp. 27–48). Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Critchley, S. (2008). The Book of Dead Philosophers. New York: Vitage Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Forst, R. (2012). “Toleration”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2012 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2012/entries/toleration/.

  • Gorski, P., Kyumn, D., Tropey, J., & VanAnterpen, J. (2012). The Post-Secular in Question. In P. Gorski, D. Kyumn, J. Tropey, & J. VanAnterpen, The Post-Secular in Question (1st ed., pp. 1–22). New York: New York University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gross, N. (2008). Richard Rorty: The making of an American intellectual. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Guignon, C. B, & Hiley, D. R. (1992). Biting the Bullet: Rorty on Private and Public Morality. In A. Malachowski, J. Burrows, & R. Rorty. Reading Rorty (pp. 339–364). Oxford, UK: B. Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (2008). Between Naturalism and Religion. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hadot, P. (2002). What Is Ancient Philosophy?. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hall, S., & Du Gay, P. (1996). Questions of Cultural Identity. London: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harris, S. (2005). The End of Faith: Religion, Terror, and the Future of Reason. London: Norton and Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hatab, L. (2008). Nietzsche’s ‘On the Genealogy of Morality’. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Herrera Lima, M. (2013). The Anxiety of Contingency. In C. Calhoun, E. Mendieta, & J. VanAntwerpen, Habermas and Religion (pp. 49–71). Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • House, D. (1994). Without God or His Doubles. Leiden: E.J. Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lafonte, C. (2013). Religion and the Public Sphere: What Are the Deliberative Obligations of Democratic Citizenship?. In C. Calhoun, E. Mendieta, & J.VanAntwerpen, Habermas and Religion (pp. 230–248). Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Latour, B. (2011). A Cautious Prometheus? A Few Steps toward a Philosophy of Design with Special Attention to Peter Sloterdijk. In W. Schinkel & L. Schinkel, Medias Res Peter Sloterdijk’s Spherological Poetics of Being (1st ed., pp. 7–28). Amsterdam: Amsterdam University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacCulloch, D. (2010). A History of Christianity: The First Three Thousand Years. London: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Malachowski, A. (1992). Deep Epistemology without Foundations (in Language). In A. Malachowski, J. Burrows, & R. Rorty, Reading Rorty (pp. 139–155). Oxford, UK: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Malachowski, A. (2002). Richard Rorty. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McKibben. B. (2000). The End of Nature. Gloucester: Peter Smith Publisher.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mendieta, E. (2012a). A Letter on Überhumanismus: Beyond Posthumanism and Transhumanism. In S. Elden, Sloterdijk Now (pp. 57–76). Cambridge, UK: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Menko Pogge, T. W. & Kosch, M. (2007). John Rawls: His Life and Theory of Justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Milbank, J. (2006). Theology and Social Theory: Beyond Secular Reason. London: Blackwell Publishing.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mouffe, C. (2010). Deliberative Democracy or Agnostic Pluralism? In J. Gripsurd, H. Moe, A. Molander, & G. Murdock, The Idea of the Public Sphere (1st ed., pp. 270–278). New York: Lexington Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, F. (1997). Philosophical Writings. Edited by: Reinhold Grimm & Carolune Molina. New York: The Continuum Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nojeim, M. (2004). Gandhi and King: The Power of Nonviolent Resistance. Westport, CT: Praeger.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (2010). The Idea of Public Reason Revisited. In J. Gripsurd, H. Moe, A. Molander, & G. Murdock, The Idea of the Public Sphere (1st ed., pp. 205–234). New York: Lexington Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (2011). Political Liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robbins, J. W. (2011). Richard Rorty: A Philosophical Guide to Talking about Religion. In Rorty, R., An Ethics for Today (pp. vii–xxii). New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, R. (1982). Consequences of Pragmatism. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, R. (1993). Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, R. (1999). Philosophy and Social Hope, London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, R. (2003). Religion in the Public Square: A Reconsideration. Journal Of Religious Ethics, 31 (1), 141–149.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, R. (2005). Anticlericalism and Atheism. In S. Zabala, The Future of Religion: Richard Rorty and Gianni Vattimo (1st ed., pp. 29–41,). New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, R. (2007b). Philosophy as Cultural Politics: Philosophical Papers Vol. 4. Cambridge [England]: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, R. (2008). Objectivity, Relativism, and Truth. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, R. (2011). An Ethics for Today, New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, R. (2015). Richard Rorty 1997 on Democracy and Philosophy. YouTube. Retrieved 24 September 2015, from https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=Azeqs20Watw

  • Rorty, R., & Mendieta, E. (2006). Take Care of Freedom and Truth will Take Care of Itself. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosati, M., & Stoeckl, K. (2012). Multiple Modernities and Postsecular Societies. Farnham, Surrey, England: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryerson, J. (2006). The Quest for Uncertainty: Richard rorty’s Pilgrimage in Take Care of Freedom and Truth Will Take Care of Itself. California: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sloterdijk, P. (1987). Critique of Cynical Reason. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sloterdijk, P. (2009). Rules for the Human Zoo: A Response to the Letter on Humanism. Environment And Planning D: Society And Space, 27(1), 12–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sloterdijk, P. (2013a). You Must Change Your Life: On Anthropotechnics. London: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sloterdijk, P. (2013b). In the World Interior of Capital: For a Philosophical Theory of Globalisation. Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, J. K. A. (2012). Secular Liturgies and the Prospects for a ‘Post-Secular’ Sociology of Religion. P. S. Gorski, D. Kyuman Kim, J. Torpey, & J. VanAntwerpen, The Post-Secular in Question, New York: New York University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stout, J. (2004). Democracy and Tradition. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stout, J. (2010). Rorty on Rligion and Politics. In R. Auxier & L. Hahn, The Philosophy of Richard Rorty (pp. 523–545). Chicago: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, C. (2007). A Secular Age, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, C. (2010). Challenging Issues about the Secular Age. Modern Theology, 26(3), 404–416.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, C. (2011). Why We Need a Radical Redefinition of Secularism. In E. Mendieta, & J. VanAntwerpen, The Power of Religion in the Public Sphere (1st ed., pp. 34–59). New York: Columbia University

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Niekerk, A. (2013). Pragmatism and Religion. In A. Malachowski, The Cambridge Companion to Pragmatism (1st ed., pp. 300–323). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Wolterstorff, N. (1997). The Role of Religion in Decision and Discussion of Political Issues, In R. Audi, & N. Wolterstroff, Politics in Religion in the Public Square (pp. 67–121), London: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Hashemi, M. (2017). The Primacy of Training over Truth: From Rorty to Sloterdijk. In: Theism and Atheism in a Post-Secular Age. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-54948-4_9

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics