Skip to main content

The Timing of Development

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Time of Nature and the Nature of Time

Part of the book series: Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science ((BSPS,volume 326))

  • 986 Accesses

Abstract

The question of whether it is possible to fit together the developmental and evolutionary explanations raises a number of difficulties. In a sense, it is possible to consider that the problems concerning the development of the individual have nothing to do with those related to the evolution of organisms over time (Wallace B, Can embryologists contribute to an understanding of evolutionary mechanisms? In: Bechtel W (ed) Integrating scientific disciplines: case studies from the life sciences. Springer. pp 149–163. Retrieved from http://link.springer.com/content/pdf/10.1007/978-94-010-9435-1_9.pdf, 1986). If one describes the development as the temporal trajectory of an individual from the zygote to adult, then the timescale of the individual development appears to be radically different from the evolutionary time scale. This chapter aims to show that the time dimension is an essential element to explain the proximal mechanism of development, and that it remains unspecified if not still largely ignored by biologists. I suggest that by focusing on the characters rather than on the “developmental stages”, developmental biology, while approaching evolution, nonetheless and paradoxically lost sight of the actual temporal dimension its process (Beer, G.R. (de) 1930. Embryology and evolution. Gloucestershire: Clarendon Press; Hamburger V, Hamilton HL, J Morphol 88(1):49–92, 1951). Therefore, consideration and characterization of the timing of development remain to be done: it requires to analyze its peculiarities and the way they have been, or may be apprehended. This focus on the developmental time will allow us to emphasize the importance of time for the explanation of the developmental process.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 119.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Wallace did not explicitly referred to the term “incommensurability” in the article, but to the term “incompatibility.” However, the picture he uses to illustrate his argument (those of a well-known analogy of an optical illusion, an example used by psychologists: a sketch, where you might see in one moment an old woman, in the next a beautiful young lady, but at no time both images simultaneously) implicitly features incommensurability (see Wallace 1986, p. 163).

  2. 2.

    See Ricqlès’, Chap. 11 in this volume.

  3. 3.

    We distinguish “evolutionist explanations” with “evolutionary explanations”. “Evolutionist explanations” are linked to the geneticists’ view on biological explanations, whereas “evolutionary explanations” include both geneticists and developmentalists’ view on these same biological explanations.

  4. 4.

    Developmental systems biology uses computer simulation of multicellular development as a research methodology to understand the function of the very complex processes involved in the development of organisms. This includes simulation of cell signaling, multicellular interactions and regulatory genomic networks in development of multicellular structures and processes (e.g., French flag model by L. Wolpert 1969).

  5. 5.

    Notion used in biology to characterize the traits or set of traits that distinguish one species, one family, one plant/animal from another. The set of observable characters from an organism is its phenotype, which is both due to hereditary factors (genotype) and changes in the environment.

  6. 6.

    Caspar F. Wolff is known as the “father of embryology” (see Needham 1959).

  7. 7.

    “Ontogeny” and “phylogeny” were the terms used (mainly before Darwin’s theory of evolution by the means of natural selection) to characterize and distinguish the developmental process from the evolution of species process.

  8. 8.

    Meckel-Serres law attempted to provide a link between comparative embryology and a “pattern of unification” in the organic world. They argued that fetal deformities result when development prematurely stops. These arrests characterized lower life forms, through which higher order organisms progress during normal development. The Meckel-Serres law stipulates that the embryos of higher order organisms progress through successive stages in which they resemble lower level forms. (http://embryo.asu.edu/pages/meckel-serres-conception-recapitulation, L. O’Connell 2013)

  9. 9.

    I refer to this notion of “geneto-developmental biology” instead of those of developmental biology to highlight the fact that developmental biology, from the beginning, has mainly focused on genetics and molecular biology and not so much on non-genetic processes of development.

  10. 10.

    For example, the following video shows the development of a salamander) https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/File:Embryonic_development_of_a_salamander,_filmed_in_the_1920s.ogv.

  11. 11.

    Adam R. Navis (2007) has recently shown that: “the main requirements of [Hamburger & Hamilton’s] project were that the stage had to be easily identifiable by visible features, and they required the smallest possible differences between the features to avoid confusion” (Concerning this question see more at: http://embryo.asu.edu/pages/stages-chick-development#sthash.leTBR20X.dpuf).

  12. 12.

    Virchow was, in the mid-nineteenth century, at the origin of the cellular theory.

  13. 13.

    In the Naturphilosophie, a philosophical trend initiated by German philosophers (Goethe, Kant, Schelling, Hegel…) in the second half of the eighteenth century which influenced Haeckel’s theorization (see Schmitt 2004).

  14. 14.

    See Huneman’s Chap. 14 in this volume.

  15. 15.

    See Tassy’s Chap. 12 in this volume.

  16. 16.

    Allometry studies the relationship of body size to shape and anatomy. It was popularized by D’Arcy Thompson’s book, On Growth and Form, in 1917 and then further developed, through statistical analysis (J. Huxley 1932).

  17. 17.

    Hamburger and Hamilton (1951) argued, “the preparation of a series of normal stages of the chick embryo […] are proving to be increasingly valuable in medical research, as in work on viruses and cancer.” Their main purpose was clearly not to establishing phylogenies between species but rather to establish a standardized view of the development of some animal models.

  18. 18.

    Stravinsky (1962, p. 54), quoted in DeLone and Wittlich. (Eds.) (1975, Chap. 3).

  19. 19.

    The concept refers to the fact that “cells acquire positional identities as in a coordinate system and then interpret this information according to their genetic constitution and developmental history” (Wolpert 1994) (e.g. the concept allows to understand cellular differentiation of cells genetically identical).

  20. 20.

    The hourglass model refers to a model in which “a constant decay or buildup of products from an initial time point is used to control timing, with threshold levels of the product being used as cues to initiate developmental events” (Reiss 2003, p. 364).

  21. 21.

    This notion of clock is different from Gould’s “clock model”. In the present case, the model is used to describe differentiation processes (e.g. somitogenesis in vertebrates: the process by which somites, blocks of mesoderm that give rise to a variety of connective tissues, are formed). The model describes processes of differentiation over time as the result of oscillating expression of particular genes.

  22. 22.

    Recently some studies have been developed which focuses on the timing of transcription and its importance for development, particularly concerning “transcriptional synchrony” (the fact that many genes are transcripted exactly at the same time) (e.g. Lagha et al. 2013). Few years ago, studies have been focusing on the isolation of “heterochronic genes” to assess developmental timing (e.g. Moss 2007, Poethig 2009, Frasch 2008).

  23. 23.

    See Huneman’s Chap. 14 in this volume.

  24. 24.

    See Ricqlès’s Chap. 11 in this volume.

References

  • Abzhanov, A. 2013. Von Baer’s law for the ages: Lost and found principles of developmental evolution. Trends in Genetics 29 (12): 712–722.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alberch, P. 1985. Problems with the interpretation of developmental sequences. Systematic Biology 34 (1): 46–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alberch, P., S.J. Gould, G.F. Oster, and D.B. Wake. 1979. Size and shape in ontogeny and phylogeny. Paleobiology 5 (3): 296–317.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alperson, P. 1980. “Musical time” and music as an “art of time”. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 38 (4): 407.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Amundsen, R. 2001. Adaptation and development. In Adaptationism and development, ed. S.H. Orzack and E. Sober. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Amundson, R. 2005. The changing role of the embryo in evolutionary thought: Roots of evo-devo. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Arauco, I. 1990. Review the time of music by J Kramer. College Music Symposium 30 (1): 153–156.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ariew, A. 2003. Ernst Mayr’s ‘ultimate/proximate’ distinction reconsidered and reconstructed. Biology and Philosophy 18 (4): 553–565.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Banerjee, D., and F. Slack. 2002. Control of developmental timing by small temporal RNAs: A paradigm for RNA-mediated regulation of gene expression. Bioessays 24 (2): 119–129.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bateson, P., P.P.G. Bateson, and P. Gluckman. 2011. Plasticity, robustness, development and evolution. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Beatty, J. 1994. The proximate/ultimate distinction in the multiple careers of Ernst Mayr. Biology and Philosophy 9 (3): 333–356.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beer, G.R. (de) 1930. Embryology and evolution. Gloucestershire: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beer, G.R. (de) (2007[1940]). Embryos and Ancestors. Oxford: Caven Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bock von Wülfingen, B., C. Brandt, S. Lettow, and F. Vienne. 2015. Temporalities of reproduction: Practices and concepts from the eighteenth to the early twenty-first century. History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 37 (1): 1–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Calcott, B. 2006. Major transitions in biological organisation. At the Australian National University, Made Available in DSpace on 2011-01-04. https://digitalcollections.anu.edu.au/handle/1885/49391.

  • Craver, C.F., and L. Darden. 2013. In search of mechanisms: Discoveries across the life sciences. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, E.H. 1991. Spatial mechanisms of gene regulation in metazoan embryos. Development 113 (1): 1–26.

    Google Scholar 

  • DeLone, R., and G.E. Wittlich, eds. 1975. Aspects of twentieth-century music. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dettlaff T.A., Igntatieva G.M. and Vassetzky S.G. (1987). The Problem of Time in Developmental Biology. Its Study by the Use of Relative Characteristics of Development Duration. Sov. Sci. Rev. Ser. F. Physiol., Gen., Biol. 1. pp. 1–88.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fox Keller, E. 1996. Refiguring life: Metaphors of twentieth-century biology. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frasch, M. 2008. A matter of timing: MicroRNA-controlled temporal identities in worms and flies. Genes & Development 22 (12): 1572–1576.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gluecksohn-Schoenheimer, S. 1938. The development of two tailless mutants in the house mouse. Genetics 23 (6): 573–584.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gottlieb, G. 1993. Forword. In Developmental time and timing, ed. G. Turkewitz and D.A. Devenny, ix–x. Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S.J. 1977. Ontogeny and phylogeny. Harvard: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S.J. 1988. The uses of heterochrony. In Heterochrony in evolution, ed. M. L. McKinney, 1–13. Springer US. Retrieved from http://link.springer.com/chapter/10.1007/978-1-4899-0795-0_1.

  • Haeckel, E.H. 1866. Generelle Morphologie der Organismen allgemeine Grundzuge der organischen Formen-Wissenschaft, mechanisch begrundet durch die von Charles Darwin reformirte Descendenz-Theorie von Ernst Haeckel: Allgemeine Entwickelungsgeschichte der Organismen kritische Grundzuge der mechanischen Wissenschaft von den entstehenden Formen der Organismen, begrundet durch die Descendenz-Theorie (Vol. 2). Verlag von Georg Reimer. Retrieved from http://books.google.com/books?hl=fr&lr=&id=RxmNSuKRp54C&oi=fnd&pg=PR26&dq=E+Haeckel+1866&ots=Lf2OIeXsKw&sig=nupCPpSKeNFVnjGUzf9CVL9HJdo.

  • Hall, B.K. 1999. Evolutionary developmental biology. New York: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hall, B.K., and W.M. Olson. 2003. Keywords and concepts in evolutionary developmental biology. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamburger, V., and H.L. Hamilton. 1951. A series of normal stages in the development of the chick embryo. Journal of Morphology 88 (1): 49–92.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hanken, J. 2015. Is heterochrony still an effective paradigm for contemporary studies of evo-devo? In Conceptual change in biology, ed. A. Love, 97–110. New York: Springer. Retrieved from.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hubaud, A., and O. Pourquié. 2014. Signalling dynamics in vertebrate segmentation. Nature Reviews Molecular Cell Biology 15 (11): 709–721.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huneman, P. 2015. Diversifying the picture of explanations in biological sciences: Ways of combining topology with mechanisms. Synthese: 1–32.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huxley, J. 1932. Problems of relative growth. New York: L. MacVeagh, The Dial Press. Retrieved from http://archive.org/details/problemsofrelati00huxl.

  • Johannsen, W. 1911. The genotype conception of heredity. The American Naturalist 45 (531): 129–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, M.H., and M.L. Day. 2000. Egg timers: How is developmental time measured in the early vertebrate embryo? BioEssays 22 (1): 57–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keibel, F. 1910. Normentafeln zur Entwicklungsgeschichte der Wirbelthiere. Vol. Hft.11. Jena: Fischer. Retrieved from http://www.biodiversitylibrary.org/item/35263.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kramer, J.D. 1988. The time of music: New meanings, new temporalities, new listening strategies. New York: Schirmer Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lagha, M., J.P. Bothma, E. Esposito, S. Ng, L. Stefanik, C. Tsui, J. Johnston, et al. 2013. Paused Pol II coordinates tissue morphogenesis in the Drosophila embryo. Cell 153 (5): 976–987.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laland, K.N., J. Odling-Smee, and S.F. Gilbert. 2008. EvoDevo and niche construction: Building bridges. Journal of Experimental Zoology Part B: Molecular and Developmental Evolution 310 (7): 549–566.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laland, K.N., K. Sterelny, J. Odling-Smee, W. Hoppitt, and T. Uller. 2011. Cause and effect in biology revisited: Is Mayr’s proximate-ultimate dichotomy still useful? Science 334 (6062): 1512–1516.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, E. 1961. Cause and effect in biology. Science 134 (3489): 1501–1506.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moss, E.G. 2007. Heterochronic genes and the nature of developmental time. Current Biology 17 (11): R425–R434.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKinney, M.L. 1999. Heterochrony: Beyond words. Paleobiology 25(2): 149–53. doi:10.1017/S0094837300026464.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Müller-Wille, S., and H.-J. Rheinberger. 2012. A cultural history of heredity. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Navis, A.R. 2007. Stages of chick development. Embryo Project Encyclopedia. Retrieved from http://embryo.asu.edu/pages/stages-chick-development#sthash.leTBR20X.dpuf.

  • Needham, J. 1959. A history of embryology. New York: Abelard-Schuman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nerlich, G. 1979. What can geometry explain? British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 30 (1): 69–83.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Connell, L. 2013. The Meckel-Serres conception of recapitulation. Embryo Project Encyclopedia. Retrieved from http://embryo.asu.edu/pages/meckel-serres-conception-recapitulation#sthash.NNU7SA1p.dpuf.

  • Poethig, R.S. 2009. Small RNAs and developmental timing in plants. Current Opinion in Genetics & Development 19 (4): 374–378.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pourquié, O. 2003a. The segmentation clock: Converting embryonic time into spatial pattern. Science 301 (5631): 328–330.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pourquié, O. 2003b. A biochemical oscillator linked to vertebrate segmentation. In Origination of organismal form: Beyond the gene in developmental and evolutionary biology, ed. G.B. Müller and S.A. Newman, 183–194. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raff, R.A., and G.A. Wray. 1989. Heterochrony: Developmental mechanisms and evolutionary results. Journal of Evolutionary Biology 2 (6): 409–434.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reiss, J.O. 1989. The meaning of developmental time: A metric for comparative embryology. American Naturalist 134: 170–189.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reiss, J.O. 2003. Time. In Keywords and concepts in evolutionary developmental biology, ed. B.K. Hall and W.M. Olson, 358–367. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Richardson, M.K., J. Hanken, M.L. Gooneratne, C. Pieau, A. Raynaud, L. Selwood, and G.M. Wright. 1997. There is no highly conserved embryonic stage in the vertebrates: Implications for current theories of evolution and development. Anatomy and Embryology 196 (2): 91–106.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Richardson, M.K. 1995. Heterochrony and the phylotypic period. Developmental Biology 172: 412–421.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenberg, A. 2008. Darwinian reductionism: Or, How to stop worrying and love molecular biology. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmitt, S. 2004. Histoire d’une question anatomique : La répétition des parties. Paris: Muséum National d’Histoire Naturelle.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, K.K. 2001. Heterochrony revisited: The evolution of developmental sequences. Biological Journal of the Linnean Society 73 (2): 169–186.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stockhorst, S. 2006. Zeitkonzepte. Zur Pluralisierung des Zeitdiskurses im langen 18. Jahrhundert, Das achtzehnte Jahrhundert. Zeitschrift der Deutschen Gesellschaft zur Erforschung des achtzehnten Jahrhunderts 30: 157–164.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stravinsky, I. 1962. Autobiography. New York: W.W. Norton & Co., Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tadros, W., and H.D. Lipshitz. 2009. The maternal-to-zygotic transition: A play in two acts. Development 136 (18): 3033–3042.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tessmar-Raible, K., F. Raible, and E. Arboleda. 2011. Another place, another timer: Marine species and the rhythms of life. Bioessays 33 (3): 165–172.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tills, O.S., D. Rundle, and J.I. Spicer. 2013. Parent–offspring similarity in the timing of developmental events: An origin of heterochrony? Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B: Biological Sciences 280 (1769): 20131479.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turkewitz, G., and D.A. Devenny, eds. 1993. Developmental time and timing. Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Velhagen, W.A. 1997. Analyzing developmental sequences using sequence units. Systematic Biology 46 (1): 204–210.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Virchow, R.L.K. 1860. Cellular pathology as based upon physiological and pathological history: Twenty lectures delivered in the Pathological Institute of Berlin during the months of February, March, and April, 1858. Birmingham: Classics of Medicine Library.

    Google Scholar 

  • Von Baer, C.E. 1827. De ovi mammalium et hominis genesi epistolam (etc.). Leop. Voss. Retrieved from http://books.google.com/books?hl=fr&lr=&id=Ns5YAAAAcAAJ&oi=fnd&pg=PT9&dq=von+Baer+(1827&ots=BqtyPqiOux&sig=3jIfun4lj-bNbqNQQmSZjUpeMUA.

  • Waddington, C.H. 1940. The genetic control of wing development in Drosophila. Journal of Genetics 41 (1): 75–113.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wallace, B. 1986. Can embryologists contribute to an understanding of evolutionary mechanisms? In Integrating scientific disciplines: Case studies from the life sciences, ed. W. Bechtel, 149–163. Springer. Retrieved from http://link.springer.com/content/pdf/10.1007/978-94-010-9435-1_9.pdf.

  • Wellmann, J. 2015. Folding into being: Early embryology and the epistemology of rhythm. History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 37 (1): 17–33.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • West-Eberhard, M.J. 2003. Developmental plasticity and evolution. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolff, C.F. 1774. Theoria generationis. Halae, ad Salam: Typis et sumtu Io.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolpert, L. 1969. Positional information and the spatial pattern of cellular differentiation. Journal of Theoretical Biology 25 (1): 1–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wolpert, L. 1994. Positional information and pattern formation in development. Developmental Genetics 15 (6): 485–490.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. 2014. Scientific explanation. In The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, ed. E. N. Zalta. Retrieved from http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2014/entries/scientific-explanation/.

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank Christophe Bouton and Philippe Huneman for their fruitful comments on previous versions of this manuscript as well as Michel Vervoort for his precious advices and references. This work was supported financially by the “Who Am I?” Laboratory of Excellence (ANR-11-LABX-0071) funded by the French government through its “Investments for the Future” Program operated by the French National Research Agency (ANR) under grant no. ANR-11-IDEX-005-02, as well as by the ANR Program EXPLABIO (Explanations in Evolutionary Biology) under grant no ANR-13-BSH3-0007.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Antonine Nicoglou .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Nicoglou, A. (2017). The Timing of Development. In: Bouton, C., Huneman, P. (eds) Time of Nature and the Nature of Time. Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science, vol 326. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-53725-2_15

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics