Skip to main content

Pragmatism, Apriority, and Modality: C.I. Lewis Against Russell’s Material Implication

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Pragmatism in Transition
  • 198 Accesses

Abstract

On the standard interpretation of Lewis’s criticism of Russell, Lewis takes his own account of strict implication to be more intuitive than the paradoxes to which Russell’s material implication leads. This chapter argues against the standard interpretation by showing that Russell’s views are not counterintuitive, but that appeals to “intuition” are not the substance of Lewis’s criticism of Russell. Lewis’s debate with Russell undergoes two main phases. In the first phase, Lewis argues both that the logic of material implication fails to represent correctly the distinction between correct and incorrect inferences and that the logic of material implication is not useful. In the second phase, Lewis argues that Russell’s explication of implication neither coheres fully with Russell’s deductive practices nor can Russell avoid appealing to strict implications. A better understanding of the Russell-Lewis dispute points to a conception of the nature of logic: it must be possible for logical principles to play a practical role in reasoning, else logic becomes disconnected from rational thought and discourse.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See also Russell’s glosses on *2.21, “ \( {\sim}p \supset \left( {p \supset q} \right)\)” and *2.02, “ \(p \supset \left( {q \supset p} \right)\)” of Principia Mathematica.

  2. 2.

    See Lewis (1973, p. 86) and Lewis (1986, p. 133).

  3. 3.

    So far as I know, Lewis himself never uses “paradox” to characterize material implication; his terms of criticism are milder: some theorems of Principia are “somewhat startling,” “suspicious to common sense” (1912, p. 522), and “peculiar” (1917, p. 351).

  4. 4.

    I defend this interpretation in Shieh (forthcoming-a).

  5. 5.

    Some of these complexities are explored in the fine discussion of Lewis on strict implication in Curley (1975).

  6. 6.

    I set out the full account of Lewis’s view of logic in Shieh (forthcoming-a), from which the discussion in this essay is derived.

  7. 7.

    See, inter alia, Bruce Kuklick (1977, Chapter 28), Cheryl Misak (2013, Chapter 10), and Murray Murphey (2006).

  8. 8.

    For more on this metaphysics of propositions, see Griffin (1980), Hylton (1990), and Cartwright (2003).

    Russell does not explicitly provide an account truth in virtue of logical structure in Principles, but I provide a sketch in Shieh (forthcoming-a). See Almog (1989) for a similar idea.

  9. 9.

    This attempt to understand Russell through Gödel is partly justified by Gödel’s extensive interest in Russell, as evidenced by the Max-Phil Notebooks; see in particular Floyd and Kanamori (2015).

  10. 10.

    I omit Russell’s conditionalization on \(p,q,r\) being propositions.

  11. 11.

    Arguments by reductio are strictly speaking not proofs; but all such arguments can be converted into genuine proofs.

  12. 12.

    We’ll see later that Lewis says, “Pragmatically,…material implication is an obviously false logic” (Lewis 1914, p. 246; emphasis mine).

  13. 13.

    This passage suggests that Lewis takes all of Russell’s axioms and theorems to have a double use, but it is plausible that Russell supposes only some of them to have that double use. In Principles this is shown, for example, by the fact that an axiom of the calculus of relations is “implication is a relation,” which surely has no use as a rule of inference. In Principia it’s unclear how the axiom of reducibility could have such a double use. Of course what is important for Lewis is that the axioms and theorems of the propositional calculus have this double use.

  14. 14.

    I’m indebted to Curley (1975) for my formulation of this problem for material implication.

  15. 15.

    So practical apriority is not the same thing as Lewis’s pragmatic conception of the a priori, as articulated in the (1923) paper of that title and in Mind and the World-Order (1929). Practically a priori knowledge of implications and disjunctions is not claimed to be independent of the given, or attained in virtue of being postulated by the mind and so not constrained by the given.

  16. 16.

    Russell and Lewis were not alone among philosopher-logicians of the turn of the twentieth century in holding that logical principles must be useful actual reasoning; two other prominent examples are C. S. Peirce and F. P. Ramsey. For discussion of Peirce’s views, see Cheryl Misak (1988, 2013). In forthcoming work she also discusses Ramsey’s views and their connection to Peirce.

  17. 17.

    In Shieh (2012) and Shieh (Lewis 2013) I had ascribed a different argument to Lewis. I’m grateful to Tom Stoneham for pressing me on the details of that other argument, for in attempting to clarify the details I came to see both the problems of that argument and how the argument given here works.

  18. 18.

    Two prominent examples are Royce (1908, pp. 702ff.) and Royce (1914, pp. 122ff.).

  19. 19.

    See Lewis (1916) and Lewis (1918, Chapter 6, sections 3 & 4).

  20. 20.

    I’m grateful to Cheryl Misak for urging me to clarify my view of Lewis’s conception of truth. I tell much of the long story in Shieh (forthcoming-b).

Bibliography

  • Almog, J. (1989). Logic and the World. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 18, pp. 197–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1950). Logical Foundations of Probability. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, R. (2003). Russell and Moore, 1898–1905. In The Cambridge Companion to Bertrand Russell, ed. Nicholas Griffin, pp. 108–127. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Curley, E. M. (1975). The Development of Lewis’s Theory of Strict Implication. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 16, pp. 517–527.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Floyd, J., and A. Kanamori (2015). Gödel Vis-À-Vis Russell: Logic and Set Theory to Philosophy. In Kurt Gödel: Philosopher-Scientist, eds. Gabriella Crocco and Eva-Maria Engelen. Aix-en-Provence: Presses Universitaires de Provence.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gödel, K. (1964). What is Cantor’s Continuum Problem? In Philosophy of Mathematics: Selected Readings, eds. Paul Benacerraf and Hilary Putnam, pp. 258–273. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffin, N. (1980). Russell on the Nature of Logic (1903–1913). Synthese, 45, pp. 117–188.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hylton, P. (1990). The Logic of Russell’s Logicism. In The Analytic Tradition, eds. David Bell and Neil Cooper, pp. 137–172. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuklick, B. (1977). The Rise of American Philosophy 1860–1930. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, C.I. (1912). Implication and the Algebra of Logic. Mind, 21, pp. 522–531.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. (1913a). A New Algebra of Implications and Some Consequences. The Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods, 10, pp. 428–438.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. (1913b). Interesting Theorems in Symbolic Logic. The Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods, 10, pp. 239–242.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. (1914). The Calculus of Strict Implication. Mind 23(90): 240–247.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. (1915). A Too Brief Set of Postulates for the Algebra of Logic. The Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods, 12, pp. 523–525.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. (1916). Types of Order and the System Σ. The Philosophical Review, 25, pp. 407–419.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. (1917). The Issues Concerning Material Implication. The Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods, 14, pp. 350–356.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. (1918). A Survey of Symbolic Logic. Semicentennial Publications of the University of California, 1868–1918. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. (1921). The Structure of Logic and its Relation to Other Systems. The Journal of Philosophy, 18, pp. 505–516.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. (1923). A Pragmatic Conception of the a Priori. The Journal of Philosophy, 20, pp. 169–177.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. (1929). Mind and the World-Order: Outline of a Theory of Knowledge. New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. (1930). Logic and Pragmatism. In Collected Papers of C.I. Lewis, eds. John D. Goheen, and John L. Mothershead, pp. 1–19. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. K. (1973). Counterfactuals. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. (1986). On the Plurality of Worlds. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Misak, C. (1988). Truth and the End of Inquiry: A Peircean Account of Truth. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. (2013). The American Pragmatists. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G. E. (1899). The Nature of Judgment. Mind, 8(30), pp. 176–193.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murphey, M. (2006). C.I. Lewis: The Last Great Pragmatist. Albany, NY: SUNY Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. (1981). Mathematical Logic. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Royce, J. (1908). The Problem of Truth in Light of Recent Discussion. In William James and Other Essays on the Philosophy of Life, ed. Josiah Royce. London: The Macmillan Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. (1914). The Principles of Logic. In Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences, ed. Arnold Ruge, pp. 310–378. London: The Macmillan Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1903). The Principles of Mathematics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. (1905). Necessity and Possibility. In Foundations of Logic, 1903–1905, Bertrand Russell, Alasdair Urquhart, and A. C. Lewis, 4: pp. 507–520. London; New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. (1906). The Theory of Implication. American Journal of Mathematics, 28, pp. 160—202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. (1919). The Philosophy of Logical Atomism. The Monist, 29, pp. 32–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shieh, S. (2012). Logic, Modality, and Metaphysics in Early Analytic Philosophy: C.I. Lewis Against Russell. In Categories of Being: Essays on Metaphysics and Logic, ed. Lila Haaparanta and Heikki Koskinen, pp. 293–318. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • ———. (2013). Modality. In The Oxford Handbook of the History of Analytic Philosophy, ed. Michael Beaney, pp. 1043–1081. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. (forthcoming-a). Necessity Lost: Modality and Logic in Early Analytic Philosophy. Vol. 1. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. (forthcoming-b). Necessity Regained: Modality and Logic in Early Analytic Philosophy. Vol. 2. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whitehead, A., and B. Russell (1910). Principia Mathematica. 1st ed. Vol. 1. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiener, N. (1916). Mr. Lewis and Implication. Journal of Philosophy, 13, pp. 656–662.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Thanks are due to members of the audiences to which earlier versions of this essay were presented: Ian Proops’s seminar at the University of Michigan, a seminar at Auburn University, the Orange Beach Epistemology Workshop, the Relativization of the A Priori Symposium at l’Université de Bordeaux Montaigne, and the Beijing International Conference on Analytic Philosophy at Beijing Normal University. In particular, I’m grateful to the comments and suggestions of Ian Proops, Arata Hamawaki, Kelly Jolley, Richard Fumerton, Juliet Floyd, Jim O’Shea, and Tom Stoneham. I would like to thank Cheryl Misak for comments on an earlier version of this chapter, as well as letting me see her forthcoming work on the influence of American pragmatism on early twentieth-century philosophy in Cambridge, England. Special thanks are due to Jean-Philippe Narboux, Timur Uçan, and Henri Wagner for creating such a splendid symposium at Bordeaux.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Shieh, S. (2017). Pragmatism, Apriority, and Modality: C.I. Lewis Against Russell’s Material Implication. In: Olen, P., Sachs, C. (eds) Pragmatism in Transition . Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-52863-2_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics