Skip to main content

Abstract

In this chapter, the authors discuss the oddness effects arising from certain kinds of scalar sentences and review two main accounts to the oddness of these sentences: an account that explains oddness as an effect of a contextually contradictory scalar implicature and an alternative account that explains oddness based on the pragmatic usability of alternatives. They discuss the oddness behavior of conjunctive variants of the original cases which have been argued to be problematic for the account based on the mismatching scalar implicature. They argue that such variants are similarly problematic for the alternative account. They contribute a novel observation that the oddness of the conjunctive variants is not as stable as that of the original cases. Finally, they sketch a possible account of the oddness of these cases based on a relevance implication procedure from the entire conjunctive sentence to single conjuncts.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 89.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    A third approach to oddness is proposed in Katzir and Singh (2015). We leave a discussion of their approach against the conjunction problem for future research.

  2. 2.

    An alternative proposal within the scalar implicature approach is in Meyer (2013). In essence, the way she accounts for the oddness of sentences like (5) is also as a mismatch between common knowledge and scalar implicatures; but, differently from Magri, she allows two possible implicatures for (5): more precisely, (5) can have the implicature also generated by Magri in (7) or the weaker epistemic implicature in (8). In either case it is easy to see that they conflict with the piece of common knowledge that if some of the players won, then all of them did.

    1. (7)

      It’s not true that all of the Portugal players won Euro 2016.

    1. (8)

      It’s not true that the speaker thinks that all of the Portugal players have won Euro 2016.

    As we will show below, Meyer’s variant of the account of oddness based on the mismatching scalar implicatures has the same problem as Magri’s version with the conjunctive case.

  3. 3.

    The approach based on a mismatching scalar implicature with common knowledge has also been challenged on various other grounds. Criticisms of Magri’s theory are presented in, e.g., Schlenker (2012), Katzir and Singh (2013), Romoli (2012) and Meyer (2013). In particular, Schlenker proposes to account for the oddness of cases such as (5) based on the notion of a mismatching scalar implicature with access to common knowledge. His idea has been challenged in Pistoia-Reda (2017), with respect to cases involving positive quantifiers, and in Magri (this volume) in connection with cases based on Hirschberg ordered sets.

  4. 4.

    Notice that Spector, unlike Magri, also predicts that (9) should give rise to oddness when uttered, for the same reason that explained the oddness of (5) above: the alternative, i.e. (5), is contextually equivalent to the target sentence. And indeed (9) also doesn’t sound unquestionably felicitous, especially when compared with sentences such as 13 or 14.

    1. (13)

      The Portugal players have won Euro 2016

    1. (14)

      Portugal has won Euro 2016.

  5. 5.

    According to his intuition, the formally analogous (20) of (5) can be rebuffed with the text in (22), which is not the case for (21), formally analogous to (18). This behavior is taken by him as evidence that only (20), and not (21), generates the inference that not all of the boys ate the cake.

    1. (20)

      Some of the boys ate the cake

    1. (21)

      Some of the boys ate the cake and the ice-cream

    1. (22)

      You are wrong: the cake was actually eaten by all of the boys

  6. 6.

    Meyer’s version of the scalar implicature approach is also in trouble when accounting for the conjunction case in (18). This is because the procedure can generate even more non-problematic implicatures for (18): the same as Magri’s in (27) and the weaker one in (28). And neither of them contradicts common knowledge.

    1. (27)

      Not all of Portugal players have won Euro 2016 and are tall.

    1. (28)

      It’s not true that the speaker thinks that all of Portugal players have won Euro 2016 and are tall.

  7. 7.

    Magri (2016) also discusses data that similarly point to the instability of the oddness of the conjunctive cases: he considers cases like (31) and submits that they are more felicitous than their counterpart without the contextual manipulation introduced by the preceding sentence.

    1. (31)

      The Portugal players have won Euro 2016. Some of them have won Euro 2016 and are tall.

  8. 8.

    See Gotzner and Romoli (2016) and Crnic (2016) for discussion of some problematic cases of Fox’s constraint.

  9. 9.

    This possibility seems to us to be in line with the proposal in Katzir and Singh (2015). In their proposal, the oddness of the original cases is derived based on the violation of some discourse conditions, in particular the question and the answer conditions.

References

  • Chierchia, Gennaro, Danny Fox, and Benjamin Spector. 2012. Scalar Implicature as a Grammatical Phenomenon. In Semantics: An International Handbook of Natural Language Meaning, ed. C. Maienborn, K. von Heusinger, and P. Portner, vol. 3, 2297–2331. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crnic, Luka. 2016. A Brief Remark on Formal Alternatives to, and Scalar Implicatures of, Sentences with Multiple Scalar Terms. MS Hebrew University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fox, Danny. 2007. Free Choice and the Theory of Scalar Implicatures. In Presuppositions and Implicatures in Compositional Semantics. Palgrave Studies in Pragmatics, Language and Cognition, ed. Uli Sauerland and Penka Stateva. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gotzner, Nicole, and Jacopo Romoli. 2016. The Scalar Inferences of Strong Scalar Terms Under Negative Quantifiers and Constraints on the Theory of Alternatives. MS ZAS/Ulster University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawkins, John. 1991. On (in)Definite Articles: Implicatures and (un)Grammaticality Prediction. Journal of Linguistics 27(2): 405–442.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heim, Irene. 1991. Artikel und definitheit. In Semantik: Ein internationales Handbuch der Zeitgenössischen Forschung, ed. Armin Von Stechow and Dieter Wunderlich, 487–535. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horn, Laurence. 1972. On the Semantic Properties of Logical Operators in English. Ph.D. Thesis, UCLA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Katzir, Roni, and Raj Singh. 2013. Constraints on the Lexicalization of Logical Operators. Linguistics and Philosophy 36(1): 1–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Katzir, Roni, and Raj Singh. 2015. Economy of Structure and Information: Oddness, Questions, and Answers. In Proceedings of Sinn und Bedeutung, ed. Eva Csipak and Hedde Zeijlstra, vol. 19, 302–319.

    Google Scholar 

  • Magri, Giorgio. 2009. A Theory of Individual-Level Predicates Based on Blind Mandatory Scalar Implicatures. Natural Language Semantics 17(3): 245–297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Magri, Giorgio. 2011. Another Argument for Embedded Scalar Implicatures Based on Oddness in Downward Entailing Environments. Semantics and Pragmatics 4: 6–1.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Magri, Giorgio. 2016. Two Puzzles Raised by Oddness in Conjunction. Journal of Semantics 33(1): 1–17.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meyer, Marie-Christine. 2013. Ignorance and Grammar. Ph.D. Thesis, Massachusetts Institute of Technology.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pistoia-Reda, Salvatore. 2014. Semantica e pragmatica linguistica. Tracce di normalità nelle implicature scalari. Biblioteca di testi e studi. Roma: Carocci.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pistoia-Reda, Salvatore. 2017. Contextual Blindness in Implicature Computation. Natural Language Semantics. doi: 10.1007/s11050-016-9131-6.

    Google Scholar 

  • Romoli, Jacopo. 2012. Obligatory Scalar Implicatures and Relevance. Snippets 25: 11–12.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rooth, Mats. 1992. A Theory of Focus Interpretation. Natural Language Semantics 1(1): 75–116.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sauerland, Uli. 2004. Scalar Implicatures in Complex Sentences. Linguistics and Philosophy 27(3): 367–391.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schlenker, Philippe. 2012. Maximize Presupposition and Gricean Reasoning. Natural Language Semantics 20(4): 391–429.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spector, Benjamin. 2007. Aspects of the Pragmatics of Plural Morphology: On Higher-Order Implicatures. In Presupposition and Implicature in Compositional Semantics, 243–281. New York: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Spector, Benjamin. 2014. Scalar Implicatures, Blindness and Common Knowledge: Comments on Magri (2011). In Pragmatics, Semantics and the Case of Scalar Implicatures. Palgrave Studies in Pragmatics, Language and Cognition, ed. Salvatore Pistoia-Reda, 146–169. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, Robert. 1978. Assertion. In Pragmatics, ed. Peter Cole, 315–332. New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Pistoia-Reda, S., Romoli, J. (2017). Oddness and Conjunction. In: Pistoia-Reda, S., Domaneschi, F. (eds) Linguistic and Psycholinguistic Approaches on Implicatures and Presuppositions. Palgrave Studies in Pragmatics, Language and Cognition. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-50696-8_3

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-50696-8_3

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Palgrave Macmillan, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-50695-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-50696-8

  • eBook Packages: Social SciencesSocial Sciences (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics