Blindness, Short-Sightedness, and Hirschberg’s Contextually Ordered Alternatives: A Reply to Schlenker (2012)

  • Giorgio Magri
Chapter
Part of the Palgrave Studies in Pragmatics, Language and Cognition book series (PSPLC)

Abstract

Magri (MIT dissertation, 2009b; Nat Lang Semant 17(3):245–297, 2009a; Semant Pragmat 4:1–51, 2011) argues that scalar implicatures are blind to any contextual information. Schlenker (Nat Lang Semant 20(4):391–429, 2012, sections 3 and 4) objects that contextual Blindness is too strong an assumption because of the contextually ordered alternatives documented in Hirschberg (A theory of scalar implicature. Garland, New York, 1991). He thus submits that the computation of scalar implicatures is not blind but just contextually “short-sighted”: it can ignore certain pieces of common knowledge, but it is not required to ignore all of it. In this chapter, the author shows that Schlenker’s proposal is a technical mistake: Short-sightedness is provably equivalent to Blindness under natural assumptions on the set of scalar alternatives. Short-sightedness thus provides no new ammunition against Hirschberg’s challenge. The author then takes a closer look at the challenge, through some initial evidence, that contextually ordered alternatives are restricted and dependent on specific lexical choices. He conjectures that these choices share the property of introducing more logical structure than meets the eye, thus possibly providing the logical ordering required by Blindness (or the equivalent Short-sightedness). If this conjecture turns out to be correct, contextual ordering is never relevant to scalar implicatures, as indeed predicted by Blindness (or the equivalent Short-sightedness).

Keywords

Scalar implicatures Oddness Contextually ordered alternatives Gricean reasoning Common knowledge 

Notes

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank Gennaro Chierchia, Danny Fox, Salvatore Pistoia-Reda, Paolo Santorio, and Philippe Schlenker for useful comments. The chapter has also benefitted from comments and discussion at the Exhaustivity Workshop held at MIT on September 10, 2016.

References

  1. Abusch, Dorit, and Mats Rooth. 2004. Empty Domain Effects for Presuppositional and Non-presuppositional Determiners. In Context Dependence in the Analysis of Linguistic Meaning, ed. Barbara Partee and Hans Kamo. Amsterdam: Elsevier.Google Scholar
  2. Beaver, David, and Brady Clark. 2008. Sense and Sensitivity. Cambridge: Wiley-Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Beavers, John. 2008. Scalar Complexity and the Structure of Events. In Event Structures in Linguistic Form and Interpretation, ed. Johannes Dölling, Tatjana Heyde-Zybatow, and Martin Schäfer, 245–265. New York: Mouton de Gruyter.Google Scholar
  4. Beavers, John. 2013. Aspectual Classes and Scales of Change. Linguistics 51: 681–706.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Chierchia, Gennaro. 2004. Scalar Implicatures, Polarity Phenomena and the Syntax/pragmatics Interface. In Structures and Beyond, ed. Adriana Belletti. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  6. Chierchia, Gennaro, Danny Fox, and Benjamin Spector. 2012. The Grammatical View of Scalar Implicatures and the Relationship Between Semantics and Pragmatics. In Handbook of Semantics, ed. Paul Portner, Claudia Maienborn, and Klaus von Heusinger, vol. 3. New York: Mouton de Gruyter.Google Scholar
  7. de Jong, Franciska, and Henk Verkuyl. 1991. Generalized Quantifiers: The Properness of Their Strength. In Generalized Quantifiers in Natural Language, ed. John van Benthem and Alice ter Meulen, 21–43. Dordrecht: Foris.Google Scholar
  8. Fox, Danny. 2000. Economy and Semantic Interpretation. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  9. Fox, Danny. 2007. Free Choice and the Theory of Scalar Implicatures. In Presupposition and Implicature in Compositional Semantics, ed. Uli Sauerland and Penka Stateva, 71–120. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Gazdar, Gerald. 1979. Pragmatics: Implicature, Presupposition and Logical Form. New York: Academic Press.Google Scholar
  11. Gazdar, Gerard. 1980. Pragmatics and Logical Form. Journal of Pragmatics 4: 1–13.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Geurts, Bart. 2007. Existential Import. In Existence: Semantics and Syntax, ed. Ileana Comorovski and Klaus von Heusinger, 253–271. Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
  13. Geurts, Bart. 2010. Quantity Implicatures. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Harnish, Robert M. 1979. Logical Form and Implicature. In Linguistic Communication and Speech Acts, ed. Kent Bach and Robert M. Harnish, 313–391. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  15. Hart, H. 1951. A Logician’s Fairy Tale. The Philosophical Review 60: 198–212.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Hay, Jennifer, Christopher Kennedy, and Beth Levin. 1999. Scalar Structure Underlies Felicity in Degree Achievements. In Proceedings of Semantics and Linguistic Theory IX, ed. Tanya Matthews and Devon Strolovitch, 127–144. Ithaca: CLC Publications.Google Scholar
  17. Hirschberg, Julia. 1991. A Theory of Scalar Implicature. Outstanding Dissertations in Linguistics. New York: Garland.Google Scholar
  18. Horn, L. 1972. On the Semantic Properties of Logical Operators in English. UCLA Dissertation. Distributed by IULC.Google Scholar
  19. Horn, Larry. 1997. All John’s Children Are as Bald as the King of France: Existential Import and the Geometry of Opposition. In CLS 33, 155–179.Google Scholar
  20. Horn, Laurence R. 2005. The Border Wars: A Neo-Gricean Perspective. In Where Semantics Meets Pragmatics, ed. Ken Turner and Klaus von Heusinger. Oxford: Elsevier.Google Scholar
  21. Kempson, Ruth M. 1975. Presupposition and the Delimitation of Semantics. Cambridge Studies in Linguistics, vol. 15. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  22. Kennedy, Christopher, and Beth Levin. 2008. Measure of Change: The Adjectival Core of Degree Achievements. In Adjectives and Adverbs: Syntax, Semantics, and Discourse, ed. Louise McNally and Christopher Kennedy, 156–182. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  23. Kratzer, Angelika. in progress. The Event Argument and the Semantics of Verbs. University of Massachusetts at Amherst; available online at www.semanticarchive.net.
  24. Krifka, Manfred. 1998. The Origins of Telicity. In Events and Grammar, ed. Susan Rothstein, 197–235. Dordrecht: Kluwer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Lappin, Shalom, and Tanya Reinhart. 1988. Presuppositional Effects of Strong Determiners: A Processing Account. Linguistics 26: 1021–1037.Google Scholar
  26. Levinson, Stephen C. 1983. Pragmatics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  27. Magri, Giorgio. 2009a. A Theory of Individual-Level Predicates Based on Blind Mandatory Scalar Implicatures. Natural Language Semantics 17(3): 245–297. doi:10.1007/s11050-009-9042-x.Google Scholar
  28. Magri, Giorgio. 2009b. A Theory of Individual-Level Predicates Based on Blind Mandatory Scalar Implicatures. Constraint Promotion for Optimality Theory. MIT Dissertation.Google Scholar
  29. Magri, Giorgio. 2011. Another Argument for Embedded Scalar Implicatures Based on Oddness in Downward Entailing Contexts. Semantics and Pragmatics 4: 1–51. doi:10.3765/sp.4.6.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Pistoia-Reda, Salvatore. 2017. Contextual Blindness in Implicature Computation. Natural Language Semantics. doi: 10.1007/s11050-016-9131-6.Google Scholar
  31. Prince, E.F. 1982. Grice and Universality: A Reappraisal. In Proceedings of the Penn Linguistics Colloquium.Google Scholar
  32. Russell, Bertrand. 1904. On Denoting. Mind 14: 479–493.Google Scholar
  33. Schlenker, Philippe. 2012. “Maximize Presupposition” and Gricean Reasoning. Natural Language Semantics 20(4): 391–429. doi:10.1007/s11050-012-9085-2.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Spector, Benjamin. 2016. Comparing exhaustivity operators. Semantics and Pragmatics 9.Google Scholar
  35. Strawson, Peter Frederick. 1950. On Referring. Mind 59: 320–344.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Walker, Ralph C.S. 1975. Conversational Implicatures. In Meaning, Reference, and Necessity: New Studies in Semantics, ed. S. Blackburn. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© The Author(s) 2017

Authors and Affiliations

  • Giorgio Magri
    • 1
  1. 1.SFL UMR 7023, (CNRS, University of Paris 8, UPL)ParisFrance

Personalised recommendations