Skip to main content

Evil and a Worthwhile Life

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Reflections on Ethics and Responsibility

Abstract

In this chapter, I examine Peter French’s account of moral evil and his claim that it ought to be understood as a human action that jeopardizes another person’s (or group’s) aspirations to live a worthwhile life (or lives). In addition, French argues that a person’s life is worthwhile if what he or she really gives a damn about satisfies some condition(s) of value. Although I find French’s definition of moral evil to be correct, his account of what makes a life worthwhile is too demanding. In order to salvage his definition of evil, I offer an alternate definition of a worthwhile life. To this end, I shall examine the definitions of meaningful, ☻, valuable, and good lives while distinguishing each from a worthwhile life. Subsequently, I turn to a discussion of what does not make a life worthwhile and how this understanding helps us clarify the nature of evil.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See French (1992, 2011).

  2. 2.

    One might suppose that even though such creatures cannot actually achieve a worthwhile life because they lack the capacity for care or for caring about things of value, they could nevertheless aspire to live a worthwhile life and hence be considered victims of evil on French’s account. However, French’s and Frankfurt’s analysis of caring shows that the capacity to aspire is dependent on the capacity to care. An individual can want or like something in a temporally discrete moment without consideration of the future, but caring about something is inherently prospective. Insofar as an individual’s cares structure her identity and bind together the moments of her life, aspirations for that life are rooted in what she cares about. See Frankfurt (1998, 83). I am grateful to Andrew Khoury for raising this point.

  3. 3.

    See also Fuji (2009).

  4. 4.

    One wonders whether Eichmann’s performance at his trial was sincere. New evidence has been uncovered to indicate that it was not. Bettina Stangneth challenges Arendt’s portrayal of Eichmann as a thoughtless, yet ambitious, bureaucrat. In a compelling retelling of his story she proposes that his actions were the intentional acts of a “fanatical Nazi” ardently committed to the annihilation of the Jews (Stangneth 2015, 7). Despite this revelation about Eichmann’s true motivation, we need not abandon the contention that evil may be caused by banal motives. A significant number of empirical studies support the position that acts of grave wrongdoing begin with ordinary and comprehensible motives and beliefs. The well-known Milgram experiments and the Stanford Prison Experiment support this observation. Each set of experiments showed how easily ordinary individuals subject their peers to severe harm. Furthermore, psychologists Melvin Lerner and Carolyn Simmons reveal that when confronted with seemingly inexplicable suffering, people tend to believe that the suffering victim deserves her fate (1966). Similarly, Vicky Wilkins and Jeffery Wenger discovered that individuals who think the world is a just place, that is, those who believe that both suffering and prosperity are deserved rather than in large part a matter of luck, are more likely to oppose social policies aimed at rectifying injustices (2014). Still in another experiment, Zick Rubin and Letitia Anne Peplau discovered that people who believe that evil and injustice has a purpose or justification are more likely to support authoritarian political leaders (1975). These studies indicate that one need not have cruel or malicious beliefs or motivations in order to cause injustice or even evil. See also Imhoff and Banse (2009).

  5. 5.

    See also Singer (2004); Kekes (2005).

  6. 6.

    One way to examine evil is to say that it exists, that it plays a prominent role in human history, and even in philosophy, but that it cannot be defined. See Susan Neiman (2002). Neiman defends this approach by arguing that the problem of evil understood in both religious and secular contexts was the pressing problem from modern philosophy to the present. However she also insists that a precise definition of evil is neither possible nor helpful.

  7. 7.

    See also Kekes (1990); Vetlesen (2005); Card (2010); Russell (2012, 2014) for additional harm-based accounts of evil.

  8. 8.

    There are also numerous accounts of evil that attempt to define the concept by reference to features of the perpetrator—specific intentions, motives, desires, or a lack thereof. For example, see Garrard (1998, 2002); or Singer (2004). For a clarifying overview of different kinds of approaches to theories of evil, see Russell 2014. Although perpetrator-based theories are compelling, they also risk limiting evil acts to a single psychological cause. Since my current goal is an analysis of French’s theory of evil, I shall not further evaluate the advantages and disadvantages of these different approaches to defining evil in this chapter.

  9. 9.

    French’s emphasis on the suffering of victims is not limited to physical pain. He acknowledges that “in some of its more dastardlier instantiations, [evil] may be entirely psychological” (2011,62).

  10. 10.

    See also French (2001).

  11. 11.

    See also Nagel (1986); Sartre (2007). Of course, understanding the issue of creating individual meaning in a meaningless world is central to the Existentialist project.

  12. 12.

    For a psychological analysis suggesting that meaningfulness is subjective, see Hicks and King (2009).

  13. 13.

    I exclude money since only on very rare occasions will an individual evaluate the worthwhileness of continuing her life based upon money. It is not unheard of to do so, but it is not the norm for determining whether continuing one’s life is worth one’s while.

  14. 14.

    “Subjective determination” means that there are no standards independent of the individual’s desires, beliefs, or mental states to determine whether her life is worth her time and effort to continue. Of course a person may determine her life to be worthwhile because it is meaningful, valuable, significant, or good, but she need not do so on these grounds. For a discussion of subjective and objective theories of meaningfulness, see Metz (2013).

  15. 15.

    See also Camus (1991).

  16. 16.

    I am indebted to Richard Taylor for this example, although Taylor employs this example to arrive at a different conclusion. See Taylor (1970).

  17. 17.

    Although the martyr-case shows this conceptual division most clearly, we do not need to appeal to such dramatic cases to support the thesis that a meaningful life is not necessarily worthwhile. There are individual examples that also support this claim. For example, George Eastman, the founder of Eastman-Kodak, was a major philanthropist and helped popularize amateur photography. He also committed suicide. He shot himself twice in the chest and left a note that read: “To my friends: My work is done, Why wait? G.E.” (Etkind, 12). The actor George Sanders, who has two stars on the Hollywood Walk of Fame, swallowed five bottles of barbiturates and left a suicide note that read: “Dear World, I am leaving because I am bored. I feel I have lived long enough. I am leaving you with your worries in this sweet cesspool. Good luck.” (Etkind, 67).

  18. 18.

    See also: Parfit (1984); Smuts (2013, 2014).

  19. 19.

    To name two prominent examples: The authors Jean Amery and Tadeusz Borowski committed suicide years after surviving the Holocaust.

  20. 20.

    The definitions of a valuable or significant life are important in their own right and deserve further scrutiny. However, given the scope of this chapter, my current goal is to show that these kinds of life are conceptually and substantively distinct from a worthwhile life, not to provide a robust analysis of their defining characteristics.

  21. 21.

    Almost all lives impact others. Therefore, most lives are significant for at least one other person. For a life to be significant for human history or for all of us it must surpass some threshold of impact. Further, if a life is valuable it may be necessarily significant since by engendering good for others one impacts them. I leave this discussion for another time.

  22. 22.

    For example: Plato The Republic 508e2, Aristotle Nicomachean Ethics, 1098a7-1099a12, Epicurus Letter to Monoeceus, Epictetus Enchiridion.

  23. 23.

    It is not that I do not think that philosophical reflection is an important ingredient to a good life. Rather, I think that good lives can be reached in many ways. Further, being excellent in rationality or virtue is no guarantee of attaining a good life. See also, Kekes (1990).

  24. 24.

    See also Flanagan (1996). Here he discusses meaningfulness while referring without distinction to worth, value, meaning, and wellbeing.

  25. 25.

    See also: McDermott (1991), Cottingham (2003); Bortolotti (2009); Smuts (2013); and May (2015). Although Smutz argues that worthwhileness and meaningfulness are distinct, he conflates worth/worthiness and worthwhileness. Notable exceptions are: Metz (2012), where he explicitly distinguishes the meaningful and the worthwhile; Trisel (2007), where he distinguishes among different ways of testing whether a life is worthwhile before concluding the best test is whether an individual would choose to be born into this world and continue her life.

  26. 26.

    French may be open to the suggestion that one can live a worthwhile life even if one gives a damn about something that does not satisfy external conditions of value. See French (2011, 192). However, I make the further claim that one can live a worthwhile life even if one does not give a damn about anything at all.

  27. 27.

    By definition wantons do not care about their cares and therefore would only care about things of value by mere luck. Also, I am assuming for argument’s sake that animals do not care about things of value, but I readily acknowledge that this may not be the case. If it is not, then they already belong to the class of moral persons that French has argued can be victims of evil.

  28. 28.

    Hobbes famously describes the summum malum as fear of a violent death. I would extend this notion to include not only that which makes death unbearable, but that which makes life unbearable as well.

  29. 29.

    Paul Formosa characterizes evil in terms of “life-wrecking harm”. He defines this harm as that which interferes “with a person’s ability to live a full and complete life” (2008, 229). This definition is similar to French’s and is likewise too strong.

References

  • Arendt, Hannah. 1964. Eichmann in Jerusalem: A report on the banality of evil. New York: Viking Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. 1984. Nicomachean ethics. In The complete works of Aristotle, ed. Jonathan Barnes, vol. Two. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Badhwar, Neera K. 2014. Well-being: Happiness in a worthwhile life. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Baier, Kurt. 1997. Problems of life and death. Amherst: Prometheus Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benetar, David. 2006. Better never to have been: The harm of coming into existence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bishop, Michael. 2015. The good life: Unifying the philosophy and psychology of well-being. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bortolotti, Lisa, eds. 2009. Philosophy and happiness. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Browning, Christopher. 1992. Ordinary men: Reserve police battalion 101 and the final solution in Poland. New York: Harper Collins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Camus, Albert. 1991. The Myth of Sisyphus and Other Essays. Trans. Justin O’Brian. New York: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Card, Claudia. 2002. The atrocity paradigm: A theory of evil. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2010. Confronting evils: Terrorism, torture, genocide. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Clendinnen, Inga. 2002. Reading the holocaust. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cole, Phillip. 2006. The myth of evil. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cottingham, John. 2003. On the meaning of life. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Epictetus. 2004. Enchiridion. Trans. George Long. New York: Dover Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Epicurus. 2010. Letter to menoeceus. In The ethical life: Fundamental readings in ethics and moral problems, ed. Russ Shafer-Landau. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Etkind, Marc. 1997. Or not to be: A collection of suicide notes. New York: Riverhead Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flanagan, Owen. 1996. Self expressions: Mind, morals, and the meaning of life. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Formosa, Paul. 2008. A conception of evil. The Journal of Value Inquiry 42: 217–239.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt, Harry. 1998. The importance of what we care about. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • French, Peter A. 1992. Responsibility matters. Lawrence: University Press of Kansas.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2001. The virtues of vengeance. Lawrence: The University of Kansas Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2011. War and moral dissonance. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fuji, Lee Ann. 2009. Killing neighbors: Webs of violence in Rwanda. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garrard, Eve. 1998. The nature of evil. Philosophical Explorations: An International Journal for the Philosophy of Mind and Action January, No. 1: 43–60.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2002. Evil as an explanatory concept. The Monist 85(2): 320–336.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hicks, Joshua A., and Laura A. King. 2009. Meaning in life as subjective experience and a lived experience. Social and Personality Psychology Compass 3(4): 638–653.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Imhoff, Roland, and Rainer Banse. 2009. Ongoing victim suffering increases prejudice: The case of secondary anti-semitism. Psychological Science 20: 1443–1447.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kekes, John. 1990. Facing evil. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2005. The roots of evil. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lerner, Melvin J., and Carolyn H. Simmons. 1966. Observer’s reaction to the ‘innocent victim’: Compassion or rejection? Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 4(2): 203–210.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lifton, Robert Jay. 2000. The nazi doctors: Medical killing and the psychology of genocide. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Margalit, Avishai. 1996. The decent society. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • May, Todd. 2015. A significant life. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McDermott, John J. 1991. Why bother: Is life worth living? The Journal of Philosophy 88(11): 677–683.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Metz, Thaddeus. 2012. The meaningful and the worthwhile: Clarifying the relationships. The Philosophical Forum 43(4): 435–448.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013. Meaning in life: An analytic study. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, Thomas. 1986. The view from nowhere. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neiman, Susan. 2002. Evil in modern thought: An alternative history of philosophy. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, Derek. 1984. Reasons and persons. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plato. 1997. Apology. In Plato: Complete works, ed. John M. Cooper and trans. G.M.A. Grube, 17b-42. Indianapolis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rubin, Zick, and Letitia Anne Peplau. 1975. Who believes in a just world? Journal of Social Issues 31(3): 65–89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, Luke. 2012. Evil and incomprehensibility. Midwest Studies in Philosophy XVI: 62–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014. Evil: A philosophical investigation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sartre, Jean-Paul. 2007. Existentialism is a Humanism. Trans. Carol Macomber. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shklar, Judith. 1989. The liberalism of fear. In Liberalism and the moral life, ed. Nancy L. Rosenblum. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singer, Marcus. 2004. The concept of evil. Philosophy 79(308): 185–214.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singer, Peter. 1993. Practical ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smuts, Aaron. 2013. Five tests for what makes a life worth living. Journal of Value Inquiry 47: 439–459.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014. To be or never have been: Anti-natalism and a life worth living. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 17: 711–729.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stangneth, Bettina. 2015. Eichmann before Jerusalem: The unexamined life of a mass murderer. New York: Vintage Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Straus, Scott. 2006. The order of genocide: Race, power, and war in Rwanda. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, Richard. 1970. Good and evil: A new direction. New York: Prometheus Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trisel, Brooke Alan. 2007. Judging life and its value. Sorites 18: 60–75.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vetlesen, Arne Johan. 2005. Evil and human agency: Understanding collective evildoing. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Waller, James. 2002. Becoming evil. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilkins, Vicky, and Jeffery Wenger. 2014. Belief in a just world and attitudes toward affirmative action. Policy Studies Journal 42(3): 325–343.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wolf, Susan. 2010. Meaning in life and why it matters. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Zachary J. Goldberg .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Goldberg, Z.J. (2017). Evil and a Worthwhile Life. In: Goldberg, Z. (eds) Reflections on Ethics and Responsibility. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-50359-2_10

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics