Skip to main content

Boolean Descriptions

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
  • 946 Accesses

Abstract

Chapters 2 and 3 outline the nature of Boolean versus non-Boolean descriptions. While a Boolean two-valued logic with truth values “true” and “false” is best characterized by the famous “rule of the excluded middle” (or tertium non datur), non-Boolean logic violates this rule. The consequence is incompatible descriptions, which are central to the notion of complementarity. Originally imported into quantum physics by Bohr, complementary descriptions are formally related to non-commutative algebras of observables.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   99.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Banaschewski (1977) showed that Spencer Brown’s concept of a primary algebra is exactly the theory of join and addition (i.e., symmetric difference) of Boolean algebras.

  2. 2.

    Frege (1918/1919, p. 74, editor’s translation): “Neither logic nor mathematics has the task to inquire into the souls and conscious contents of individual human beings. One might rather consider it as their task to study the mind, not the minds.”

  3. 3.

    Hilbert (1931, p. 125, editor’s translation): “Through the tertium non datur logic acquires full harmony; its theorems attain such simplicity and the system of its concepts such completeness as it ought to conform to the significance of a discipline expressing the structure of all our thinking.”

  4. 4.

    See Padoa (1901, pp. 309–365). English translation quoted from van Heijenoort (1967, p. 121).

  5. 5.

    According to Bohr (1934, p. 53), our “interpretation of the experimental material rests essentially upon the classical concepts”. Bohr’s emphasis on the special role of classical physics is somewhat misleading. By a “classical description” Bohr means a description in terms of ordinary language. Important for Bohr’s arguments is only that facts have to be described in a Boolean language, but not necessarily in terms of classical physics.

  6. 6.

    Editor’s note: For the history of the concept of complementarity and its origin in psychology and philosophy see Holton (1970).

  7. 7.

    Editor’s note: In fact, complementarity is a maximal form of incompatibility, as will be discussed later in this monograph (see Sects. 3.4 and 3.5).

  8. 8.

    Strauss (1936a, 1936b, 1938, 1967, 1970, 1973) defined a logic of complementarity as a two-valued logic with restricted sentential connectivity whose propositional calculus is given by a partial Boolean algebra.

  9. 9.

    English translation by A. Stairs as The logic of propositions which are not simultaneously decidable, reprinted by Hooker (1975, pp. 135–140). A more recent translation is by M.P. Seevinck: The logic of non-simultaneously decidable propositions, arxiv.org/abs/1103.4537. Editor’s note: Specker presented a slightly revised version on March 27, 2000, in his seminar on Quantum Logic and Hidden Parameters at ETH Zurich. This version has not been translated into English so far.

  10. 10.

    Editor’s note: The particular version of Specker’s parable is a complication of the usual pairwise incompatibility of measurements in quantum physics. It expresses that compatible measurements are jointly possible pairwise but not triplewise (see Liang et al. 2011, see also Sect. 3.5.4).

  11. 11.

    Partial Boolean algebras have been used by Franz Kamber (1964) as the propositional calculus for quantum systems before Kochen and Specker (1965a, 1965b) proved that the partial Boolean structure arising in quantum theory cannot be embedded into a Boolean algebra. Compare Sect. 3.4 for more details.

References

  • Banaschewski B (1977) On G. Spencer Brown’s laws of form. Notre Dame J Form Log 18:507–509. Quoted in Sect 2.1

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Bohr N (1934) Atomic theory and the description of nature. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. Quoted in Sects 2.4, 4.6, 8.4

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Bohr N (1948) On the notions of causality and complementarity. Dialectica 2:312–319. Quoted in Sect 2.4

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Bohr N (1949) Discussion with Einstein on epistemological problems in atomic physics. In: Schilpp PA (ed) Albert Einstein: philosopher–scientist. Open Court, Evanston, pp 199–241. Quoted in Sects 2.4, 4.6

    Google Scholar 

  • Boole G (1847) The mathematical analysis of logic, being an essay towards a calculus of deductive reasoning. Macmillan, Cambridge. Quoted in Sect 2.2

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Boole G (1848) The calculus of logic. Camb Dublin Math J 3:183–198. Quoted in Sect 2.2

    Google Scholar 

  • Boole G (1849) Elementary treatise on logic not mathematical. In: Grattan-Guinness I, Bornet G (eds) George Boole. Selected manuscripts on logic and its philosophy. Birkhäuser, Basel, pp 13–41, 1997. Quoted in Sect 2.2

    Google Scholar 

  • Boole G (1854) An investigation of the laws of thought, on which are founded the mathematical theories of logic and probabilities. Macmillan, London. Quoted in Sect 2.2

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Cobern WW (1996) Worldview theory and conceptual change in science education. Sci Educ 80:579–610. Quoted in Sect 2.4

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eddington A (1920) Space, time and gravitation. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. Quoted in Sect 2.3

    Google Scholar 

  • Feyerabend P (1994) Quantum theory and our view of the world. In: Hilgevoord J (ed) Physics and our view of the world. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 149–168. Quoted in Sect 2.4

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Frege G (1918/1919) Der Gedanke. Eine logische Untersuchung. Beitr Philos Dtsch Ideal 2:58–77. Quoted in Sect 2.2

    Google Scholar 

  • von Goethe JW (2003) Faust, parts I and II, transl by Kline AS, available at www.poetryintranslation.com/PITBR/German/FaustIScenesIVtoVI.htm. Quoted in Sect 2.1

    Google Scholar 

  • Hammer PC (1969) Filters in general. In: Hammer PC (ed) Advances in mathematical system theory. Pennsylvania State University Press, London, pp 107–120. Quoted in Sect 2.5

    Google Scholar 

  • van Heijenoort J (1967) From Frege to Gödel. A source book in mathematical logic, 1879–1931. Harvard University Press, Cambridge. Quoted in Sects 2.2, 5.4, 5.6

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Hilbert D (1931) Beweis des tertium non datur. In: Nachrichten von der Gesellschaft der Wissenschaften zu Göttingen, Mathematisch-Physikalische Klasse, pp 120–125. Quoted in Sect 2.2

    Google Scholar 

  • Holton G (1970) The roots of complementarity. Daedalus 99:1015–1055. Quoted in Sect 2.4

    Google Scholar 

  • Hooker CA (1975) The logico-algebraic approach to quantum mechanics, volume I: historical evolution. Reidel, Dordrecht. Quoted in Sect 2.4

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Kamber F (1964) Die Struktur des Aussagenkalküls in einer physikalischen Theorie. Nachr Akad Wiss Gött Math-Phys Kl 10:103–124. Quoted in Sect 2.4

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Kochen S, Specker EP (1965a) Logical structures arising in quantum theory. In: Addison J, Henkin L, Tarski A (eds) The theory of models. North-Holland, Amsterdam, pp 177–189. Quoted in Sects 2.4, 3.4

    Google Scholar 

  • Kochen S, Specker EP (1965b) The calculus of partial propositional functions. In: Bar-Hillel Y (ed) Logic, methodology and philosophy of science. North-Holland, Amsterdam, pp 45–57. Quoted in Sects 2.4, 3.4

    Google Scholar 

  • Langer S (1978) Philosophy in a new key. A study in the symbolism of reason, rite, and art. Harvard University Press, Cambridge. Quoted in Sect 2.1

    Google Scholar 

  • Liang Y-C, Spekkens RW, Wiseman HM (2011) Specker’s parable of the overprotective seer: a road to contextuality, nonlocality and complementarity. Phys Rep 506:1–39. Quoted in Sect 2.4

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • McCulloch WS, Pitts W (1943) A logical calculus of the ideas immanent in nervous activity. Bull Math Biophys 5:115–133. Quoted in Sect 2.3

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • von Neumann J (1951) The general and logical theory of automata. In: Jeffress LA (ed) Cerebral mechanisms in behavior. Wiley, New York, pp 1–41. Quoted in Sect 2.3

    Google Scholar 

  • Padoa A (1901) Essai d’une théorie algébrique des nombre entiers, précédé d’une introduction logique à une théorie déductive quelconque. In: Bibliothèque du Congrès international de philosophie Paris 1900. Colin, Paris, pp 309–365. Quoted in Sect 2.2

    Google Scholar 

  • Platt JR (1956) Amplification aspects of biological response and mental activity. Am Sci 44:180–197. Quoted in Sect 2.3

    Google Scholar 

  • Polanyi M (1958) Personal knowledge. Towards a post-critical philosophy. Routledge and Kegan Paul, London. Quoted in Sects 2.4, 4.1

    Google Scholar 

  • Specker E (1960) Die Logik nicht gleichzeitig entscheidbarer Aussagen. Dialectica 14:239–246. Quoted in Sect 2.4

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Spencer Brown G (1969) Laws of form. Allen and Unwin, London. Quoted in Sects 2.1, 2.5

    Google Scholar 

  • Strauss M (1936a) Komplementarität und Kausalität im Lichte der logischen Syntax. Erkenntnis 6:335–339. Quoted in Sects 2.4, 4.6

    Google Scholar 

  • Strauss M (1936b) Zur Begründung der statistischen Transformationstheorie der Quantenphysik. Sitz Preuss Akad Wiss, Phys-Math Kl 27:382–398. Quoted in Sects 2.4, 4.6

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Strauss M (1938) Mathematics as logical syntax—a method to formalize the language of a physical theory. Erkenntnis 7:147–153. Quoted in Sects 2.4, 4.6

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Strauss M (1967) Grundlagen der modernen Physik. In: Ley H, Löther R (eds) Mikrokosmos–makrokosmos, vol 2. Akademie Verlag, Berlin, pp 55–92. Quoted in Sects 2.4, 3.4, 4.6

    Google Scholar 

  • Strauss M (1970) Intertheory relations. In: Weingartner P, Zecha G (eds) Induction, physics and ethics. Reidel, Dordrecht, pp 220–284. Quoted in Sect 2.4, 4.6

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Strauss M (1973) Logics for quantum mechanics. Found Phys 3:265–276. Quoted in Sects 2.4, 4.6

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Szent-Györgi A (1962) The persistence of the caveman. Saturday Rev 45:11. Quoted in Sect 2.3

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Primas, H. (2017). Boolean Descriptions. In: Atmanspacher, H. (eds) Knowledge and Time. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-47370-3_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics