Skip to main content

Partial Evidence in Medicine

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Philosophy of Science in Practice

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 379))

Abstract

We advance a conception of evidence in medicine that accounts for the significance of randomized clinical trials despite the fact that they are not the gold standard in clinical research. Crucial to this account is the gradualist, partial nature of evidence in medicine, and the different kinds of uncertainty that are involved throughout medical inquiry.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 119.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    This is not the place to provide a full defense of the neutrality norm, which bears on controversial issues regarding the connections between science and values (see, for instance, Lacey 1999; Mitchell 2004; Douglas 2009; Biddle 2013). But we argue below that violation of this norm has significant risks, which are better avoided.

  2. 2.

    It is also a mistake to characterize data uncertainty as the same type of uncertainty that is treated by Jeffrey’s model of conditionalization since we are not attempting to characterize uncertainty about the evidential input but uncertainty about the evidential relevance relation. Jeffrey’s model of conditionalization makes it possible to accommodate uncertainty about the truth-value of an evidential input (by allowing it to take a value less than one) but the application of this model ultimately serves to collapse a distinction between uncertainty about the truth-value of the evidential input and uncertainty about the truth-value of the hypothesis. Again, when two distinct types of uncertainty are collapsed, we are often left with inadequate tools when attempting accurate reconstructions of the process of scientific inference in actual practice.

  3. 3.

    What kind of object is then a piece of evidence? It is not clear that there is a unique answer to this question. Different things are invoked in different contexts as evidence. Different things have been—and can be—considered as evidence. A theory of evidence is monist if it admits only one kind of thing as being evidence. A theory of evidence is pluralist if it admits multiple kinds of things as being evidence. Given the diversity of sources of evidence in the sciences, not surprisingly, we favor a pluralist view. We don’t think, however, that this challenges the objectivity of evidence. After all, it’s not up to us what rules out (likely) alternatives that undermine the hypothesis under investigation. Thus, objectivity is preserved in face of this pluralism.

  4. 4.

    This is, of course, a general issue. It is possible that the new population is different from the old regarding treatment efficacy; that is, although the results were perhaps generally correct, they did not apply to the new population. This is precisely an instance of experimental uncertainty at work.

References

  • Achinstein, P. (2001). The book of evidence. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Balshem, H., et al. (2011). GRADE guidelines: 3. Rating the quality of evidence. Journal of Clinical Epidemiology, 64, 401–406.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Biddle, J. (2013). State of the field: Transient underdetermination and values in science. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 44, 124–133.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brunkhorst, F., et al. (2008). Intensive insulin therapy and pentastarch resuscitation in severe sepsis. New England Journal of Medicine, 358, 125–139.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bueno, O. (1997). Empirical adequacy: A partial structures approach. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 28, 585–610.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (2009). Evidence-based policy: What’s to be done about relevance? Philosophical Studies, 143, 127–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (2010). What are randomized controlled trials good for? Philosophical Studies, 147, 59–70.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N., & Hardie, J. (2012). Evidence-based policy: A practical guide to doing it better. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • da Costa, N. C. A., & French, S. (2003). Science and partial truth. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dellinger, P., et al. (2004). Surviving sepsis campaign: Guidelines for management of severe sepsis and septic shock. Critical Care Medicine, 32, 858–873.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dellinger, P., et al. (2008). Surviving sepsis campaign: International guidelines for management of severe sepsis and septic shock: 2008. Critical Care Medicine, 38, 296–327 (Reprinted at Critical Care Medicine 2008 Reprint, pp. 1–33).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeMets, D., Pocock, S., & Julian, D. (1999). The agonizing negative trend in monitoring of clinical trials. Lancet, 354, 1983–1988.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Douglas, H. (2009). Science, policy, and the value-free ideal. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lacey, H. (1999). Is science value free? London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Machamer, P., & Wolters, G. (Eds.). (2004). Science, values, and objectivity. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maxwell, G., & Anderson, R. (Eds.). (1975). Induction, probability, and confirmation. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, S. (2004). In Machamer & Wolters (Eds.), The prescribed and proscribed values in science policy (pp. 245–255).

    Google Scholar 

  • Reiss, J. (2014). What’s wrong with our theories of evidence? Theoria, 80, 283–306.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. (1975). In Maxwell & Anderson (Eds.), Confirmation and relevance (pp. 3–36).

    Google Scholar 

  • Van den Berghe, G., et al. (2001). Intensive insulin therapy in critically ill patients. New England Journal of Medicine, 345, 1359–1367.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van den Berghe, G., et al. (2006). Intensive insulin therapy in the medical ICU. New England Journal of Medicine, 354, 449–461.

    Google Scholar 

  • Worrall, J. (2002). What evidence in evidence based-medicine? Philosophy of Science, 69, S316–S330.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Worrall, J. (2007). Why there’s no cause to randomize. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 58, 451–488.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This work was funded by a grant from the Arsht Ethics Initiatives at the University of Miami Ethics Programs and made possible by a generous gift from philanthropist Adrienne Arsht. We are very grateful to the UM Ethics Programs and the Arsht Ethics Initiatives for their support. Thanks are also due to two reviewers for their extensive and very helpful comments on an earlier version of this paper, which led to substantial improvements.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Otávio Bueno .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Bueno, O., Neiman, R. (2017). Partial Evidence in Medicine. In: Chao, HK., Reiss, J. (eds) Philosophy of Science in Practice. Synthese Library, vol 379. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-45532-7_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics