Skip to main content

Symptom and Context: The Issue of Validity in Diagnosis

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Book cover Psychiatric Diagnosis Revisited
  • 1306 Accesses

Abstract

In this chapter Stijn Vanheule discusses how the DSM-5 takes context into account and clarifies the “kind of entity” the manual considers mental disorders to be. In the DSM-5 the context of the individual (i.e., the personal life history, social circumstances, and cultural background) is thought to play a minor moderating role in relation to symptom formation and expression. Moreover, as the manual follows a sign-based logic, it coheres with the assumption that biological irregularities lie at the basis of mental distress. The author argues that, by doing this, the DSM cultivates a naïve essentialistic view of mental disorders, which is not supported by relevant evidence. Starting from phenomenological psychiatry and Lacanian psychoanalysis, Vanheule proposes an alternative model of symptom formation. Within this model, the symptom is a multidimensional product with certain speech-act specific qualities, biological characteristics, and contextual configuration features covering characteristics that are specific of an individual, family, social context, and (sub-)culture.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 79.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Good discussions of power and discipline in contemporary psy-professions can be found in the works of Ian Parker (2010) and Nikolas Rose (1996, 1999).

  2. 2.

    Thusly so, Westen’s (2012) plea for a return to explicit prototype-based diagnosis as an alternative should be taken seriously.

  3. 3.

    Sometimes the DSM’s focus on description is characterized as “phenomenological” (e.g., Decker 2013). This is confusing since the phenomenological approach to psychopathology, as illustrated by the quote of Parnas, largely exceeds the DSM-like focus on description.

  4. 4.

    It is important to note that within various philosophical traditions the concepts of subjectivity and subject obtain different interpretations. For example, in phenomenological approaches, subjectivity is identified with conscious experience as the fundamental ground of our understanding of both the world and ourselves. This dimension of conscious experience is considered to be accessible through self-reflection, based on which a person can construct a narrative about what he lives through. In this view subjectivity is knowable and, eventually, amenable to a normative evaluation (is this person’s self-experience adequate or not?). From a Lacanian psychoanalytic point of view, by contrast, the subject qua product of self-reflexivity is not a discernible entity but a self-relating “emptity.” Self-related thoughts and speech connote who we are and what we live through, but never denote the subject. Within this view the notion of the subject refers to the multitude of signifiers, based on which self-experience is constituted and across which self-experience is fundamentally scattered; hence the idea that the subject is “divided.” Lacan does not think of the subject as a psychological or teleological instance that makes use of signifiers, but as the connotative effect of using signifiers. The subject doesn’t produce speech; speech produces the subject. Thus considered, self-reflexivity does not imply self-transparency. On the contrary, from a Lacanian point of view self-reflexivity is marked by an impossibility, which makes up the unconscious. Nevertheless, what both philosophical traditions have in common is the explicit valorization of subjectivity.

  5. 5.

    Interesting psychometric challenges for the DSM approach to mental symptoms can be found in the work of Denny Borsboom and colleagues (e.g., Borsboom and Cramer 2013).

  6. 6.

    The terms particularities and singularities are often used synonymously. I suggest distinguishing them: “particular” refers to characteristics that hold true for subgroups; “singular” refers to characteristics and events that cannot be generalized.

  7. 7.

    Lacanian psychoanalysis does not reject the idea that psychopathology is governed by laws that can be described in scientific terms, but maintains that the reflexive relation an individual has to his own condition cannot be reduced to these laws. This theoretical position does not give rise to an idealist theory of the mind in which non-material mental forces are presumed to be active, but to a so-called decentered materialism. Crucial to this Lacanian materialism is the divided subject’s relation to the Real (De Vos 2014). In this context, Lacan made a relevant distinction between nature and physics. Nature is that which determines us in how we act and through our self-reflexive attitude we can relate to it. Physics, like all other sciences, is a discourse based on which we study and intervene upon the world. Science constitutes just one way of relating to nature. It transforms our way of relating to nature, but never eliminates what is Real to a subject.

  8. 8.

    In Chap. 2 I discuss the fact that this hard work to improve the reliability of psychiatric classification was not particularly successful.

  9. 9.

    Obviously, these reflections gave rise to the appendix on cultural formulation in the DSM-5.

  10. 10.

    In a 19-page document entitled Highlights of Changes from DSM-IV-TR to DSM-5 (http://www.dsm5.org/documents/changes%20from%20dsm-iv-tr%20to%20dsm-5.pdf) all changes are reviewed. Nevertheless, several authors, like Allen Frances (2013), correctly suggest that for several disorders inclusion and exclusion criteria were subtly relaxed, thus predicting waves of inflating diagnosis. For example, whereas DSM-IV-TR indicates that a diagnosis of ADHD can be made only if symptoms are present before the age of seven, the DSM-5 indicates that the diagnosis can be made if symptoms are present before the age of 12. This “small” criterion change actually implies that the population eligible for the diagnosis actually doubled.

  11. 11.

    In the process of researching this book I contacted the DSM-5 task force chair and vice-chair, David Kupfer and Darrel Regier, asking both of them whether the scientific studies on the basis of which decisions were made about disorder criteria could be provided. Neither of them responded.

  12. 12.

    See: http://www.nimh.nih.gov/research-priorities/rdoc/nimh-research-domain-criteria-rdoc.shtml

  13. 13.

    In psychology, different emotions, like happiness, sadness, anger and anxiety, are sometimes considered as natural kinds. However, whether this is justified or not remains an object of continuous debate (Lindquist et al. 2013).

Other References

  • Adriaens, P., & De Block, A. (2013). Why we essentialize mental disorders. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 38, 107–127.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Andreasen, N. (2001). Diversity in psychiatry: Or, why did we become psychiatrists? American Journal of Psychiatry, 158, 673–675.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Beavan, V., Read, J., & Cartwright, C. (2011). The prevalence of voice-hearers in the general population: A literature review. Journal of Mental Health, 20, 281–292.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Bernstein, C. A. (2011). Meta-structure in DSM-5 process. Psychiatric News, 46(5), 7–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berrios, G. E. (1999). Classifications in psychiatry: A conceptual history. Australian and New Zealand Journal of Psychiatry, 33, 145–160.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Berrios, G. E. (2012). The 19th-century nosology of alienism: History and epistemology. In K. S. Kendler & J. Parnas (Eds.), Philosophical issues in psychiatry II – Nosology (pp. 101–117). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Berrios, G. E., & Marková, I. S. (2002). Conceptual issues. In H. D’haenen, J. A. den Boer, & P. Willner (Eds.), Biological psychiatry (pp. 9–39). Chichester: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berrios, G. E., & Marková, I. S. (2006). Symptoms: Historical perspective and effect on diagnosis. In M. Blumenfield & J. J. Strain (Eds.), Psychosomatic medicine (pp. 27–38). Philadelphia: Lippincott Williams & Wilkins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bird, A., & Tobin, E. (2010). Natural kinds. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Summer 2010 edition). Retrieved September 16, 2011, from http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2010/entries/natural-kinds/.

  • Borsboom, D., & Cramer, A. O. J. (2013). Network analysis: An integrative approach to the structure of psychopathology. Annual Review of Clinical Psychology, 9, 91–121.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Boschloo, L., van Borkulo, C. D., Rhemtulla, M., Keyes, K. M., Borsboom, D., & Schoevers, R. A. (2015). The network structure of symptoms of the diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders. PLoS ONE, 10, e0137621.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Bracken, P., Thomas, P., Timimi, S., et al. (2012). Psychiatry beyond the current paradigm. British Journal of Psychiatry, 201, 430–434.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Buchheim, A., Viviani, R., Kessler, H., et al. (2013). Changes in prefrontal-limbic function in major depression after 15 months of long-term psychotherapy. Plos One, 7, e33745.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Canguilhem, G. (1966). The normal and the pathological. Brooklyn: Zone Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Charney, D. S., Barlow, D. H., Botteron, K., et al. (2002). Neuroscience research agenda to guide development of a pathophysiologically based classification system. In D. J. Kupfer, M. B. First, & D. A. Regier (Eds.), A research agenda for DSM-V (pp. 31–83). Washington, DC: American Psychiatric Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cooper, R. (2005). Classifying madness – A philosophical examination of the diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cooper, R. (2007). Psychiatry and philosophy of science. Stocksfield: Acumen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dar-Nimrod, I., & Heine, S. J. (2011). Genetic essentialism: On the deceptive determinism of DNA. Psychological Bulletin, 137, 800–818.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • de Saussure, F. (1916). Course in general linguistics. New York: Philosophical Library.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Vos, J. (2014). Which materialism? Questioning the matrix of psychology, neurology, psychoanalysis and ideology critique. Theory and Psychology, 24, 76–92.

    Google Scholar 

  • Decker, H. (2013). The making of DSM-III. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (1991). Consciousness explained. Boston: Little Brown.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dubovsky, S. L. (2016). The limitations of genetic testing in psychiatry. Psychotherapy and Psychosomatics, 85, 129–135.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Eco, U. (1976). A theory of semiotics. London: Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Evrard, R. (2013). Psychopathology and exceptional experiences: A literature review. L’Évolution Psychiatrique, 78, 155–176.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feyaerts, J., & Vanheule, S. (2015). How to return to subjectivity? Natorp, Husserl and Lacan on the limits of reflection. Theory & Psychology, 25, 753–774.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frances, A. (2013). Saving normal – An insider’s revolt against out-of-control psychiatric diagnosis, DSM-5, big pharma, and the medicalization of ordinary life. New York: William Morrow & Harper Collins Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freud, S. (1953 [1913]). On beginning the treatment (Further recommendations on the technique of psychoanalysis I). InThe standard edition of the complete psychological works for Sigmund Freud (Vol. 12, pp. 121–144). London: Hogarth Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Good, B. J. (1994). Medicine, rationality, and experience. An anthropological perspective. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (2002). Inaugural lecture: Chair of philosophy and history of science concepts at the Collège de France, 16 January 2001. Economy and Society, 31, 1–14.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1950). Cartesian meditations. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hyman, S. E. (2010). The diagnosis of mental disorders: The problem of reification. Annual Review of Clinical Psychology, 6, 155–179.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Insel, T. (2013). Transforming diagnosis. Blogpost. Retrieved December 10, 2013, from http://www.nimh.nih.gov/about/director/2013/transforming-diagnosis.shtml.

  • Insel, T., & Cuthbert, B. (2015). Brain disorders? Precisely. Science, 348, 499–500.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Insel, T. & Lieberman, J.A. (2013). DSM-5 and RDoC: Shared interests. Blogpost. Retrieved December 11, 2013, from http://www.nimh.nih.gov/news/science-news/2013/dsm-5-and-rdoc-shared-interests.shtml.

  • Insel, T., Cuthbert, B., Garvey, M., Heinssen, R., Pine, D.S.n., Quinn, K., Sanislow, C., & Wang, P. (2010). Research Domain Criteria (RDoC): Toward a new classification framework for research on mental disorders. American Journal of Psychiatry, 167, 748–751.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jeste, D. V., Palmer, B. W., Rettew, D. C., & Boardman, S. (2015). Positive psychiatry: Its time has come. Journal of Clinical Psychiatry, 76, 675–683.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Kagan, J. (2012). Psychology’s ghosts – The crisis in the profession and the way back. New Haven/London: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kapur, S., Phillips, A. G., & Insel, T. R. (2012). Why has it taken so long for biological psychiatry to develop clinical tests and what to do about it? Molecular Psychiatry, 17, 1174–1179.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Karlsson, H. (2011). How psychotherapy changes the brain. Psychiatric Times, 28. Retrieved November 12, 2013, from http://www.psychiatrictimes.com/psychotherapy/how-psychotherapy-changes-brain.

  • Keim Campbell, J., O’Rourke, M., & Slater, M. H. (2011). Carving nature at its joints: Natural kinds in metaphysics and science. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kelleher, I., Jenner, J., & Cannon, M. (2010). Psychotic symptoms in the general population – An evolutionary perspective. British Journal of Psychiatry, 197, 167–169.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kendler, K. S., Zachar, P., & Craver, C. (2011). What kinds of things are psychiatric disorders? Psychological Medicine, 41, 1143–1150.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Kirmayer, L. J., & Crafa, D. (2014). What kind of science for psychiatry. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 8, 435.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Kirshner, L. (2009). Biopolitics and the transformation of the psychiatric subject. In S. Binkley & J. Capetillo (Eds.), A Foucault for the 21st century: Governmentality, biopolitics and discipline in the new millennium (pp. 92–104). Newcastle upon Tyne: Cambridge Scholars Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kozak, M. J., & Cuthbert, B. N. (2016). The NIMH research domain criteria initiative: Background, issues and pragmatics. Psychophysiology, 53, 286–297.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Kraemer, H. C. (2015). Research Domain Criteria (RDoC) and the DSM – Two methodological approaches to mental health diagnosis. JAMA Psychiatry, 72, 1163–1164.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Kupfer, D. J., & Regier, D. A. (2011). Neuroscience, clinical evidence, and the future of psychiatric classification in DSM-5. American Journal of Psychiatry, 168, 672–674.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Kupfer, D. J., First, M. B., & Regier, D. A. (2002). A research agenda for DSM-V. Washington, DC: American Psychiatric Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lacan, J. (1964). The seminar 1964, book XI, the four fundamental concepts of psycho-analysis. London/New York: Karnac.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lacan, J. (2006 [1947]). Presentation on psychical causality. In J. Lacan & J. A. Miller (Eds.), Écrits (pp. 123–158). New York/London: W. W. Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lacan, J. (2006 [1957]). The instance of the letter in the unconscious or reason since Freud. In J. Lacan & J. A. Miller (Eds.), Écrits (pp. 412–442). New York/London: W. W. Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lacan, J. (2006 [1959]). On a question prior to any possible treatment of psychosis. In J. Lacan & J. A. Miller (Eds.), Écrits (pp. 445–488). New York/London: W. W. Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lilienfeld, S. O., & Marino, L. (1999). Essentialism revisited: Evolutionary theory and the concept of mental disorder. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 108, 400–411.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Lindquist, K. A., Siegel, E. H., Quigley, K. S., & Battett, L. F. (2013). The hundred-year emotion way: Are emotions natural kinds or psychological constructions? Comment on Lench, Flores, and Bench (2011). Psychological Bulletin, 139, 255–263.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Marková, I. S., & Berrios, G. E. (2009). Epistemology of mental symptoms. Psychopathology, 42, 343–349.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • McNally, R. J. (2011). What is mental illness? Cambridge/London: Belknap Harvard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, J. (2001). On distinguishing methodological from radical behaviorism. European Journal of Behavioral Analysis, 2, 221–244.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nobus, D. (2000). Jacques Lacan and the Freudian practice of psychoanalysis. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paris, J., & Kirmayer, L. J. (2016). The national institute of mental health research domain criteria: A bridge too far. Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease, 204, 26–32.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Parker, I. (2010). Lacanian psychoanalysis – Revolutions on subjectivity. London/New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parnas, J. (2012). The nature of the psychiatric object and classification. In K. S. Kendler & J. Parnas (Eds.), Philosophical issues in psychiatry II – nosology (pp. 118–123). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Pechey, R., & Halligan, P. (2011). The prevalence of delusion-like beliefs relative to sociocultural beliefs in the general population. Psychopathology, 44, 106–115.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Pechey, R., & Halligan, P. (2012). Prevalence and correlates of anomalous experiences in a large non-clinical sample. Psychology and Psychotherapy: Theory, Research and Practice, 85, 150–162.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Regier, D. A., Narrow, W. E., Kuhl, E. A., & Kupfer, D. J. (2009). The conceptual development of DSM-V. American Journal of Psychiatry, 166, 645–650.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Reynolds, C. F., Lewis, D. A., Detre, T., Schatzberg, A. F., & Kupfer, D. J. (2009). The future of psychiatry as clinical neuroscience. Academic Medicine, 84, 446–450.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Rose, N. (1996). Inventing our selves – Psychology, power and personhood. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rose, N. (1999). Governing the soul – The shaping of the private self – Second edition. London/New York: Free Association Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sandifer, M. S., Hordern, A., & Green, L. M. (1970). The psychiatric interview: The impact of the first three minutes. American Journal of Psychiatry, 126, 968–973.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Stein, D. J., Phillips, K. A., Bolton, D., Fulford, K. W. M., Sadler, J. S., & Kendler, K. S. (2010). What is a mental/psychiatric disorder? From DSM-IV to DSM-V. Psychological Medicine, 40, 1759–1765.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Stoyanov, D., Machamer, P. K., Schaffner, K. F., & Rivera-Hernández, R. (2012). The challenge of psychiatric nosology and diagnosis. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice, 18, 704–709.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Trudgen, R. (2000). Why warriors lie down and die. Towards an understanding of why the Aboriginal people of Arnhem land face the greatest crisis in health and education since European contact. Darwin: Aboriginal Resource and Developmental Services Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Os, J. (2010). Are psychiatric diagnoses of psychosis scientific and useful? The case of schizophrenia. Journal of Mental Health, 19, 305–317.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Van Os, J. (2016). “Schizophrenia” does not exist. The British Medical Journal, 352, i375.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Vanheule, S. (2011). The subject of psychosis – A Lacanian perspective. London/New York: Palgrave MacMillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Vanheule, S. (2012). Diagnosis in the field of psychotherapy: A plea for an alternative to the DSM-5.x. Psychology and Psychotherapy: Theory, Research and Practice, 85, 128–142.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Verhaeghe, P. (2002). On being normal and other disorders. New York: Other Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Verhaeghe, P. (2014). What about me? – The struggle for identity in a market-based society. Victoria/London: Scribe.

    Google Scholar 

  • Watters, E. (2010). Crazy like us: The globalization of the American psyche. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weinberger, D. R., Glick, I. D., & Klein, D. F. (2015). Whither Research Domain Criteria (RDoC)? The good, the bad, and the ugly. JAMA Psychiatry, 72, 1161–1162.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Westen, D. (2012). Protoype diagnosis of psychiatric syndromes. World Psychiatry, 11, 16–21.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Wilkinson, R. G., & Pickett, L. (2009). The spirit level: Why more equal societies almost always do better. London: Allan Lane.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zachar, P. (2002). The practical kinds model as a pragmatist theory of classification. Philosophy, Psychology and Psychiatry, 9, 219–227.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Vanheule, S. (2017). Symptom and Context: The Issue of Validity in Diagnosis. In: Psychiatric Diagnosis Revisited. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-44669-1_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics