Advertisement

On Hegel’s Critique of Kant’s Subjectivism in the Transcendental Deduction

  • Dennis Schulting

Abstract

In this chapter, I expound Hegel’s critique of Kant, which he first and most elaborately presented in his early essay “Faith and Knowledge” (1802), by focusing on the criticism that Hegel levelled against Kant’s (supposedly) arbitrary subjectivism about the categories. This relates to the restriction thesis of Kant’s transcendental idealism: categorially governed empirical knowledge only applies to appearances, not to things in themselves, and so does not reach objective reality, according to Hegel. Hegel claims that this restriction of knowledge to appearances is unwarranted merely on the basis of Kant’s own principle of transcendental apperception, and just stems from Kant’s empiricist bias. He argues that Kant’s principle of apperception as the foundational principle of knowledge is in fact incompatible with his empiricism. Hegel rightly appraises the centrality of transcendental apperception for the constitution of objectivity. But he is wrong about its incompatibility with Kant’s empirical realism. By virtue of a misapprehension of the formal distinction between the accompanying ‘I think’, i.e. the analytical principle of apperception, and what Hegel calls “the true ‘I’” of the original-synthetic unity of apperception, Hegel unjustifiably prises apart the productive imagination, which is supposedly this “true ‘I’”, and the understanding, which is supposedly just a derivative, subjective form of the productive imagination; the latter, according to Hegel, is Reason or Being itself, and is the truly objective. This deflationary reading of the understanding, which hypostatises the imagination as the supreme principle, rests on a distortion of key elements of Kant’s theory of apperception. In this chapter, I show that Hegel’s charge of inconsistency against Kant, namely, Hegel’s claim that the principle of apperception as the highest principle of cognition does not comport with Kant’s restriction thesis, is the direct consequence of a psychological misreading of Kant’s subjectivism.

References

  1. Ameriks, K. 2000. Hegel’s Critique of Kant’s Theoretical Philosophy. In K. Ameriks, Kant and the Fate of Autonomy. Problems in the Appropriation of the Critical Philosophy, 267–308. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  2. Ameriks, K. 2015. Some Persistent Presumptions of Hegelian Anti-Subjectivism. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume LXXXIX: 43–60.Google Scholar
  3. Bowman, B. 2013. Hegel and the Metaphysics of Absolute Negativity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Bristow, W. 2007. Hegel and the Transformation of Philosophical Critique. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Düsing, K. 1995. Das Problem der Subjektivität in Hegels Logik, 3rd ed. Bonn: Bouvier.Google Scholar
  6. Düsing, K. 2013. Konstitution und Struktur der Identität des Ich. Kants Theorie der Apperzeption und Hegels Kritik. In K. Düsing, Subjektivität und Freiheit. Untersuchungen zum Idealismus von Kant bis Hegel, 2nd expanded ed., 143–180. Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt: Frommann-Holzboog.Google Scholar
  7. Ferrarin, A. 2016. Pensare e l’io. Hegel e la critica di Kant. Rome: Carocci.Google Scholar
  8. Görland, I. 1966. Die Kantkritik des jungen Hegel. Frankfurt a/M: Klostermann.Google Scholar
  9. Hanna, R. 2013. Kant, Hegel, and the Fate of Non-Conceptual Content. Hegel Bulletin 34 (1): 1–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Harris, H. 1977. Introduction. In G.W.F. Hegel, Faith and Knowledge, trans. and ed. W. Cerf and H. Harris, 1–50. Albany, NY: SUNY.Google Scholar
  11. Horstmann, R.-P. 2004. Die Grenzen der Vernunft. Eine Untersuchung zu Zielen und Motiven des Deutschen Idealismus, 3rd ed. Frankfurt a/M: Klostermann.Google Scholar
  12. Houlgate, S. 2005. Glauben und Wissen: Hegels immanente Kritik der kantischen Philosophie oder die (illegitime) „Ahnung eines Besseren“? In Hegel-Jahrbuch: Glauben und Wissen. Dritter Teil, ed. A. Arndt et al., 152–158. Berlin: Akademie Verlag.Google Scholar
  13. Houlgate, S. 2015. Hegel’s Critique of Kant. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume LXXXIX: 21–41.Google Scholar
  14. Kreines, J. 2015. Reason in the World. Hegel’s Metaphysics and Its Philosophical Appeal. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Longuenesse, B. 1998. Kant and the Capacity to Judge. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  16. Longuenesse, B. 2015. Hegel et la critique de la métaphysique, 2nd revised and expanded ed. Paris: Vrin.Google Scholar
  17. McDowell, J. 2009. Having the World in View: Essays on Kant, Hegel, and Sellars. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  18. Pippin, R. 1989. Hegel’s Idealism: The Satisfactions of Self-Consciousness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Pippin, R. 1993. Hegel’s Original Insight. International Philosophical Quarterly XXXIII (3): 285–295.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Pippin, R. 2005. Concept and Intuition: On Distinguishability and Separability. Hegel-Studien 39/40: 25–39.Google Scholar
  21. Pippin, R. 2014. The Significance of Self-Consciousness in Idealist Theories of Logic. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 114(2), pt. 2 (July): 145–166.Google Scholar
  22. Pippin, R. 2016. Die Aktualität des deutschen Idealismus. Berlin: Suhrkamp.Google Scholar
  23. Redding, P. 2010. Analytic Philosophy and the Return of Hegelian Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  24. Reich, K. 2001. Gesammelte Schriften, ed. M. Baum. Hamburg: Meiner.Google Scholar
  25. Schulting, D. 2009. Review of W. Bristow, Hegel and the Transformation of Philosophical Critique (Oxford UP 2007). Hegel Bulletin 59/60: 82–88.Google Scholar
  26. Schulting, D. 2012. Kant’s Deduction and Apperception. Explaining the Categories. Basingstoke and New York: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
  27. Schulting, D. 2016a. Review of S. Sedgwick, Hegel’s Critique of Kant (Oxford UP 2012). Kant-Studien 107 (2): 414–419.Google Scholar
  28. Schulting, D. 2016b. On an Older Dispute: Hegel, Pippin, and the Separability of Concept and Intuition in Kant. In Kantian Nonconceptualism, ed. D. Schulting, 227–255. London and New York: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
  29. Schulting, D. 2016c. Critical Notice of Robert Pippin’s ‘Logik und Metaphysik. Hegels “Reich der Schatten”’, Critique, https://virtualcritique.wordpress.com/2016/10/16/critical-notice-of-robert-pippins-logik-und-metaphysik-hegels-reich-der-schatten/. Accessed 16 Oct 2016.
  30. Sedgwick, S. 1992. Hegel’s Treatment of Transcendental Apperception in Kant. Owl of Minerva 23 (2): 151–163.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Sedgwick, S. 1993. Pippin on Hegel’s Critique of Kant. International Philosophical Quarterly XXXIII (3): 273–283.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Sedgwick, S. 2001. “Genuine” Versus “Subjective” Idealism in Hegel’s Jenaer Schriften. In Idealismus als Theorie der Repräsentation?, ed. R. Schumacher, 233–245. Paderborn: mentis.Google Scholar
  33. Sedgwick, S. 2005. The Emptiness of the ‘I’: Kant’s Transcendental Deduction in “Glauben und Wissen”. In Hegel-Jahrbuch: Glauben und Wissen. Dritter Teil, ed. A. Arndt et al., 171–175. Berlin: Akademie Verlag.Google Scholar
  34. Sedgwick, S. 2012. Hegel’s Critique of Kant. From Dichotomy to Identity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Verra, V. (ed.). 1981. Hegel Interprete di Kant. Naples: Prismi.Google Scholar
  36. Westphal, K. 1996. Kant, Hegel, and the Transcendental Material Conditions of Possible Experience. Bulletin of the Hegel Society of Great Britain 33 (Spring/Summer): 23–41.Google Scholar
  37. Westphal, K. 2000. Kant, Hegel, and the Fate of “the” Intuitive Intellect. In The Reception of Kant’s Critical Philosophy: Fichte, Schelling, Hegel, ed. S. Sedgwick, 283–305. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© The Author(s) 2017

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Independent ScholarCarboneraItaly

Personalised recommendations