Skip to main content

Eudaimonia and Culture: The Anthropology of Virtue

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Handbook of Eudaimonic Well-Being

Part of the book series: International Handbooks of Quality-of-Life ((IHQL))

Abstract

There have been roughly two general stages in the theorization of eudaimonia. The first is found in the long history of virtue ethics in Western philosophy, the second in recent research in economics and cognitive science on the topic of subjective well-being. In the transition from philosophical virtue ethics to the quantitative study of subjective well-being, however, an important idea has been overlooked, namely, the role of culture as an essential foundation for the realization of eudaimonia. In this paper, I therefore argue for a third phase in eudaimonic well-being research, what I call a “critical eudaimonics.” This approach reintroduces culturally situated understandings of eudaimonia through thick historical and ethnographic descriptions of virtue, wisdom, and flourishing well-being to highlight the conditions in which people actually cultivate eudaimonia in everyday life. In order to argue this, I begin with a comparison of Aristotle and Alasdair MacIntyre’s theories of virtue to provide a brief intellectual history for how modern moral philosophers came to see eudaimonia as necessarily possessing a cultural history. I then turn to recent understandings of virtue in anthropology—and my own ethnographic research on compassion—to offer a definition of eudaimonia fit for the qualitative social sciences.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 299.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 379.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 379.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    There are many reasons cited for the apparent decline in virtue ethics in the modern period (see Frede, 2013; MacIntyre, 2007; Schneewind, 1990; Slote, 2015 for important contributions). Regardless of the causes, however, it is generally recognized that Aristotelian ethics played a less obvious role in the modern period until its reemergence in the twentieth century. This resurgence of virtue was largely credited to Anscombe’s classic paper “Modern Moral Philosophy” (1958), but her views were developed, challenged, and extended by a range of philosophers from the 1970s onwards, for instance, Geach (1977), Foot (1978), Williams (1981, 1985), Nussbaum (1986, 1994), Taylor (1989), Slote (1992), Annas (1993), McDowell (1998), and Hursthouse (1999).

  2. 2.

    For an early summary of works in this area see, for instance, Ryan and Deci (2001). For more recent examples, see Huppert and So (2013), Lewis, Kanai, Rees, and Bates (2014), and Vittersø and Søholt (2011).

  3. 3.

    A good example here is Peterson and Seligman’s Character Strengths and Virtues: A Handbook and Classification (2004). This alternative DSM offers a taxonomy of virtues, which although developed initially from historical accounts of the virtues, abstracts from that to provide a universal framework that applies cross-culturally.

  4. 4.

    I owe my thanks to John Tresch for suggesting this term to me.

  5. 5.

    In regards to self-sufficiency, if one thinks a life of pleasure is the ultimate good, but one also thinks such a life would be better if one was also wise, then pleasure cannot have been that good, since it would not be self-sufficient, i.e., it would be improved by the other good of wisdom.

  6. 6.

    In his later writings, MacIntyre defends a biological and metaphysical conception of teleology. I will not address those arguments here, but for those interested see Dependent Rational Animals (1999).

  7. 7.

    It is hard to say what a moral tradition is beyond this. As Porter acknowledges, “even though MacIntyre discusses tradition extensively, he never defines the term… nor does he situate his account of tradition in the context of other recent discussions” (2003, p. 36).

  8. 8.

    See Martha Nussbaum (1999) for an exception to this view.

  9. 9.

    I have not discussed Foucault in this essay as his role has been discussed extensively elsewhere (cf. Laidlaw, 2014; Mattingly, 2014).

  10. 10.

    Thus, as Asad points out, in the tradition of Christianity, there is the institution of the medieval monastery or the Church itself (as well as the ritual practices that occur within those institutions: sermons, liturgies, etc.); the moral exemplar of Jesus Christ and the authority figures of the Church Fathers; the canonical texts (the Bible or the Rule of St. Benedict); commentaries written about these foundational texts; and the practices of faith, hope, charity, humility, prudence, obedience, and so on, that allow one to embody the virtues of that tradition.

  11. 11.

    A similar point is made by Lambek when he says: “Practice theory needs to attend to more than power, habit, or competitions of honor and taste and should attend to reasoned judgment as developed in recent accounts of Aristotle’s Ethics” (2000, p. 310).

References

  • Annas, J. (1993). The morality of happiness. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Annas, J. (2011). Intelligent virtue. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Anscombe, G. E. M. (1958). Modern moral philosophy. Philosophy, 33, 1–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. (2000). Nicomachean ethics. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Asad, T. (1993). Genealogies of religion: Discipline and reasons of power in Christianity and Islam. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Asad, T. (2009). The idea of an anthropology of Islam. Qui Parle, 17(2), 1–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foot, P. (1978). Virtues and vices and other essays in moral philosophy. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frede, D. (2013). The historic decline of virtue ethics. In D. C. Russell (Ed.), The Cambridge companion to virtue ethics (pp. 124–148). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Geach, P. T. (1977). The virtues. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hirschkind, C. (2006). The ethical soundscape: Cassette sermons and Islamic counterpublics. Columbia, NY: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huppert, F. A., & So, T. T. C. (2013). Flourishing across Europe: Application of a new conceptual framework for defining well-being. Social Indicators Research, 110(3), 837–861. doi:10.1007/s11205-011-9966-7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hursthouse, R. (1999). On virtue ethics. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laidlaw, J. (2014). The subject of virtue: An anthropology of ethics and freedom. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lambek, M. (2000). The anthropology of religion and the quarrel between poetry and philosophy. Current Anthropology, 41(3), 309–320. doi:10.1086/300143.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lambek, M. (2008). Value and virtue. Anthropological Theory, 8(2), 133–157. doi:10.1177/1463499608090788.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lambek, M. (2010). Ordinary ethics: Anthropology, language, and action. New York: Fordham University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, G. J., Kanai, R., Rees, G., & Bates, T. C. (2014). Neural correlates of the ‘Good Life’: Eudaimonic well-being is associated with insular cortex volume. Social Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience, 9(5), 615–618. doi:10.1093/scan/nst032.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, A. C. (2007). After virtue: A study in moral theory. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mahmood, S. (2001). Rehearsed spontaneity and the conventionality of ritual: Disciplines of şalat. American Ethnologist, 28(4), 827–853.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mahmood, S. (2005). Politics of piety: The Islamic revival and the feminist subject. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mattingly, C. (2010). The paradox of hope journeys through a clinical borderland. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mattingly, C. (2014). Moral laboratories: Family peril and the struggle for a good life. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (1998). Mind, value, and reality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. C. (1986). The fragility of goodness: Luck and ethics in Greek tragedy and philosophy (Cambridge paperback library). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. C. (1994). The therapy of desire: Theory and practice in Hellenistic ethics. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. C. (1999). Virtue ethics: A misleading category? The Journal of Ethics, 3(3), 163–201.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pandian, A. (2008). Tradition in fragments: Inherited forms and fractures in the ethics of South India. American Ethnologist, 35(3), 466–480. doi:10.1111/j.1548-1425.2008.00048.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pandian, A. (2009). Crooked stalks: Cultivating virtue in South India. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Peterson, C., & Seligman, M. E. P. (Eds.). (2004). Character strengths and virtues a handbook and classification. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pieper, J. (2009). Leisure: The basis of culture; The philosophical act. San Francisco: Ignatius Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Porter, J. (2003). Tradition in the recent work of Alasdair MacIntyre. In M. C. Murphy (Ed.), Alasdair MacIntyre (pp. 38–69). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Robbins, J. (2004). Becoming sinners Christianity and moral torment in a Papua New Guinea Society. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robbins, J. (2013). Beyond the suffering subject: Toward an anthropology of the good. Journal of the Royal Anthropological Institute, 19(3), 447–462. doi:10.1111/1467-9655.12044.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ryan, R. M., & Deci, E. L. (2001). On happiness and human potentials: A review of research on hedonic and eudaimonic well-being. Annual Review of Psychology, 52(1), 141–166. doi:10.1146/annurev.psych.52.1.141.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schneewind, J. B. (1990). The misfortunes of virtue. Ethics, 101, 42–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Slote, M. A. (1992). From morality to virtue. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Slote, M. A. (2015). Virtue’s turn and return. Dao, 14(3), 319–324. doi:10.1007/s11712-015-9449-7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, C. (1989). Sources of the self: The making of the modern identity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trungpa, C. (2003). In G. Carolyn Rose (Ed.), The collected works of Chögyam Trungpa (Vol. 2). Boston: Shambhala.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vittersø, J., & Søholt, Y. (2011). Life satisfaction goes with pleasure and personal growth goes with interest: Further arguments for separating hedonic and eudaimonic well-being. The Journal of Positive Psychology, 6(4), 326–335. doi:10.1080/17439760.2011.584548.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Widlok, T. (2004). Sharing by default?: Outline of an anthropology of virtue. Anthropological Theory, 4(1), 53–70. doi:10.1177/1463499604040847.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Widlok, T. (2012). Virtue. In F. Didier (Ed.), A companion to moral anthropology. Chichester, UK: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, B. (1981). Moral luck: Philosophical papers, 1973–1980. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, B. (1985). Ethics and the limits of philosophy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Francis Mckay PhD .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Mckay, F. (2016). Eudaimonia and Culture: The Anthropology of Virtue. In: Vittersø, J. (eds) Handbook of Eudaimonic Well-Being. International Handbooks of Quality-of-Life. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-42445-3_27

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-42445-3_27

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-42443-9

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-42445-3

  • eBook Packages: Social SciencesSocial Sciences (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics