Skip to main content

One True Mathematics

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Pythagorean World
  • 378 Accesses

Abstract

I have argued that the unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics in fundamental physics leads to a Pythagorean view of the world in which the underlying principles are structural, mathematical principles. This naturally raises one of the key questions which Wigner addressed in his investigation of the relationship between physics and mathematics: ‘What is mathematics?’ That is the question which I address in the next two chapters. I am particularly interested in exploring the implications of a Pythagorean view for one’s philosophy of mathematics. What should Pythagoreans believe about the nature of mathematics? What are the potential problems for this view? It seems clear that, for Pythagoreans, mathematics is necessarily true, eternal and unchanging. Pythagoreans should be realists about mathematics. They should regard the pursuit of mathematics as discovering facts about the world. They should look to mathematics as the ultimate arbiter of questions about existence and truth. It is the last point that I am mainly concerned with in this chapter: can mathematics serve as the ultimate arbiter of questions about existence and truth? More particularly, I investigate whether there is one background theory of mathematics in which any mathematical problem can be interpreted and (potentially) decided. If there is—as universalists believe—then the various disciplines of mathematics are part of one, true mathematical universe. If not—as held by pluralists—then there are alternative mathematical universes and mathematical statements may be true in some universes and false in others, not necessarily true. That would be a problem for Pythagoreanism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 99.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    One interesting exception is Harvey Friedman’s efforts to ‘reverse engineer’ textbook mathematics in order to reveal exactly what set-theoretical machinery is used (Friedman and Simpson 2000).

  2. 2.

    Following Hilbert’s famous exclamation: “No one shall expel us from the paradise which Cantor has created for us” (Boyer 1991: 570).

  3. 3.

    Let T1 and T2 be recursively enumerable axiom systems. We say that T1 is interpretable in T2 (T1 ≤ T2) when, roughly speaking, there is a translation τ from the language of T1 to the language of T2 such that, for each sentence φ of the language of T1, if T1 proves φ then T2 proves τ(φ). T1 and T2 are said to be mutually interpretable when both T1 ≤ T2 and T2 ≤ T1 (Koellner 2010: 5).

  4. 4.

    The Axiom of Infinity asserts that there are infinite sets, that is, completed infinite collections.

  5. 5.

    Cantor used the term inconsistent manifold.

  6. 6.

    Axiom systems other than ZFC may omit the Axiom of Foundation, and may even include its negation, allowing for non-well-founded sets. Such sets may be “pathological” in some sense and not suitable for some mathematical applications.

  7. 7.

    See, for example, Friedman (2010) and (2011).

  8. 8.

    The statement that ZF has any models at all is equivalent to the statement that ZF is consistent, which is an assumption that cannot be proved within ZF. This follows from Gödel’s Second Incompleteness Theorem together with his completeness theorem for first-order logic.

  9. 9.

    A set X is logically definable from parameters in Lα if there exist elements a1,…,an of Lα and a logical formula Ф(x1,…,xn) in the formal language for set theory such that X = {a Є Lα | (Lα, Є) ╞ Ф(a,a1,…,an)]} where the order (Lα, Є) is the set Lα with the membership relation Є restricted to it and ╞ is the symbol for consequence (Woodin 2010a: 3).

  10. 10.

    For example, it is not necessary for the ground model to be a countable, standard, transitive model and not all forcing extensions are cardinal preserving.

  11. 11.

    The Lowenheim–Skolem theorem says that if there exists an infinite model of PA, then there exist models of all cardinality, from countable upwards.

  12. 12.

    Note that, according to Gödel’s Second Incompleteness Theorem, such models must exist if PA is consistent because it is consistent with its own inconsistency statement.

  13. 13.

    Externalists think that all that it is needed to justify a belief is for the belief to be acquired by a reliable method (in this case, the construction of consistent mathematical theories); we don’t need to know that the method is reliable or be able to explain its reliability (Balaguer 1995: 309).

  14. 14.

    Magidor (2011: 2) also advocates this view, although he is prepared to contemplate a small number of alternative universes.

  15. 15.

    I take this to be Woodin’s modus operandi in searching for ways to distinguish inconsistent large cardinal axioms from consistent ones (Woodin 2011b) (see Sect.4.6.1 and Sect. A.6 in the appendix for clarification of this point).

  16. 16.

    Finitism is often associated with the German mathematician Kronecker, who is attributed with the statement: “God made the integers, all the rest is the work of man” (Boyer 1991: 570).

  17. 17.

    See Sect. 4.2.4, especially the quote from Gödel (1931: 181).

  18. 18.

    See Kanamori (1994: 17) for a definition of a Mahlo cardinal (N.B. the definition of large cardinals is very technical).

  19. 19.

    By Gödel’s Second Incompleteness Theorem, large cardinal axioms at the level of a strongly inaccessible or higher cardinal cannot be shown to be relatively consistent with ZFC because, if x is a strongly inaccessible or higher cardinal, then it can be shown that Vx is a model of ZFC and, thus, that ZFC is consistent (Maddy 1997: 74).

  20. 20.

    For technical reasons, Gödel thought that the resolution of the continuum hypothesis would require new axioms of an extrinsic kind (i.e. based on hitherto unknown principles). In fact, it is now known that the continuum hypothesis is independent of all remotely plausible large cardinal axioms that have been considered to date.

  21. 21.

    Here, as always, one must be careful to keep separate the concepts of proper class and set, for example, V has the property of containing all sets, but no set (and, therefore, no initial segment) can have that property.

  22. 22.

    See Koellner (2009a: 212–213) for a definition of these large cardinals.

  23. 23.

    See the discussion of Gödel’s constructible universe L in Sect. 4.2.4 for a definition of definable sets. By starting with the real numbers R and iterating the definable power set operation along the ordinals, we get the hierarchy L(R) of definable sets of reals.

  24. 24.

    See Woodin (2010a: 4) for details.

  25. 25.

    See Steel (2007) for a definition of Woodin cardinals.

  26. 26.

    See Kanamori (1994: 298) for a definition of a supercompact cardinal.

  27. 27.

    For more information on Ω-logic and its relation to full first- and second-order logic, see Koellner (2010).

  28. 28.

    The Strong Ω Conjecture is the Ω Conjecture plus a conjecture about an extended form of the Axiom of Determinacy. See Koellner (2011c: 16–17).

  29. 29.

    Note that the continuum hypothesis is just a particular case; there are other suitable sentences which could be forced to differ between Ω-complete theories of Vα.

  30. 30.

    For example, it would be correct about singular cardinals and compute their successors correctly (Woodin 2011c: 465).

  31. 31.

    According to predicativists, the natural numbers form a definite totality but the collection of all sets of natural numbers (i.e. the power set) does not. For more on predicativity, see Feferman (2005).

References

  • Balaguer, M. 1995. A Platonist Epistemology. Synthese 103: 303–325.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1998. Non-Uniqueness as a Non-Problem. Philosophia Mathematica 6: 63–84.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2009. Realism and Anti-Realism in Mathematics. In Philosophy of Mathematics (Handbook of the Philosophy of Science), edited by A.D. Irvine, 35–101. Amsterdam: Elsevier/North-Hollands.

    Google Scholar 

  • Banach, S., and A. Tarski. 1924. Sur la décomposition des ensembles de points en parties respectivement congruentes. Fundamenta Mathematicae 6: 244–277.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beall, J.C. 1999. From Full-Blooded Platonism to Really Full-Blooded Platonism. Philosophia Mathematica 7: 322–325.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyer, C. 1991. A History of Mathematics. New York: John Wiley & Sons.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cheyne, C. 1999. Problems with Profligate Platonism. Philosophia Mathematica 7: 164–177.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, P. 1963. The Independence of the Continuum Hypothesis. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America 50(6): 1143–1148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1964. The Independence of the Continuum Hypothesis II. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America 51(1): 105–110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feferman, S. 2000. Does Mathematics Need New Axioms? Proceedings of a symposium with H.M. Friedman, P. Maddy and J. Steel, Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 6: 401–413.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2005. Predicativity. In The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mathematics and Logic, edited by S. Shapiro, 590–624. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2006b. The Impact of the Incompleteness Theorems on Mathematics. Notices American Mathematical Society 53: 434–449.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2011. Is the Continuum Hypothesis a Definite Mathematical Problem? pp. 1–29, downloaded from http://logic.harvard.edu/EFI_Feferman_IsCHdefinite.pdf

  • Fraenkel, A. 1922. Zu den Grundlagen der Cantor-Zermeloschen Mengenlehre. Mathematische Annalen 86: 230–237.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fraenkel, A., and Y. Bar-Hillel. 1958. Foundations of Set Theory. Amsterdam: North-Holland Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. 1879. Begriffsschrift, eine der arithmetischen nachgebildete Formelsprache des reinen Denkens, Halle a.S.: Louis Nebert. Translation: ‘Concept Script, a formal language of pure thought modelled upon that of arithmetic’, by S. Bauer-Mengelberg in Jean Van Heijenoort (ed.), 1967, From Frege to Gödel: A Source Book in Mathematical Logic, 1879–1931, Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, H. 2001. Does Normal Mathematics Need New Axioms?, downloaded from http://www.math.osu.edu/~friedman/manuscripts.html , pp. 1–12.

  • ———. 2002. Philosophy 532: Philosophical Problems in Logic Lecture 1. Presented at Princeton University 9/25/02, downloaded from http://www.math.osu.edu/~friedman/manuscripts.html , pp. 1–107.

  • ———. 2010. Boolean Relation Theory and Incompleteness, downloaded from http://www.math.osu.edu/~friedman/manuscripts.html

  • ———. 2011. My Forty Years on His Shoulders. In Kurt Gödel and the Foundations of Mathematics: Horizons of Truth, edited by Matthias Baaz et al., 399–434. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, H., and S. Simpson. 2000. Issues and Problems in Reverse Mathematics. Computability Theory and Its Applications, Contemporary Mathematics 257: 127–144.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gödel, K. 1931. On Formally Undecidable Propositions of Principia Mathematica and Related Systems I. In K. Gödel Collected Works, edited by S. Feferman et al., Vol. 1, 145–195. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1986.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1940. The Consistency of the Continuum-Hypothesis. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1946. Remarks Before the Princeton Bicentennial Conference on Problems in Mathematics. In K. Gödel Collected Works, edited by S. Feferman et al., Vol. II, 150–153. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1947. What Is Cantor’s Continuum Problem? In K. Gödel Collected Works, edited by S. Feferman et al., Vol. 2, 176–187. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1953/1959. Is Mathematics Syntax of Language. In K. Gödel Collected Works, edited by S. Feferman et al., Vol. 3, 334–355. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1964. What Is Cantor’s Continuum Problem? In K. Gödel Collected Works, edited by S. Feferman et al., Vol. 2, 254–270. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamkins, J. 2011. The Set-Theoretic Multiverse, downloaded from http://arxiv.org/abs/1108.4223 , pp. 1–35.

  • Kanamori, A. 1994. The Higher Infinite: Perspectives in Mathematical Logic. Berlin: Springer-Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2008. Cohen and Set Theory. The Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 14(3): 351–378.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kanigel, R. 1991. The Man Who Knew Infinity: A Life of the Genius Ramanujan. New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koellner, P. 2009a. On Reflection Principles. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 157: 206–219.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2010. Strong Logics of First and Second Order. The Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 16: 1–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2011a. Independence and Large Cardinals. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer ed.), edited by Edward N. Zalta, downloaded from http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2011/entries/independence-large-cardinals/

  • ———. 2011b. Large Cardinals and Determinacy, downloaded from http://logic.harvard.edu/EFI_LCD.pdf , pp. 1–44.

  • ———. 2011c. The Continuum Hypothesis, downloaded from http://logic.harvard.edu/EFI_CH.pdf , pp. 1–38.

  • Koellner, P., and W. Woodin. 2009. Incompatible Ω-Complete Theories. Journal of Symbolic Logic 74: 1155–1170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levy, A., and R. Solovay. 1967. Measurable Cardinals and the Continuum Hypothesis. Israel Journal of Mathematics 5: 234–248.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Macintyre, A. 2011. The Impact of Gödel’s Incompleteness Theorems on Mathematics. In Kurt Gödel and the Foundations of Mathematics: Horizons of Truth, edited by Matthias Baaz et al., 3–26. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maddy, P. 1997. Naturalism in Mathematics. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2005. Mathematical Existence. The Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 11: 351–376.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2011. Defending the Axioms. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Magidor, M. 2011. Some Set Theories Are More Equal, downloaded from http://logic.harvard.edu/EFI_Magidor.pdf , pp. 1–26.

  • Martin, D., and J. Steel. 1994. Iteration Trees. Journal of the American Mathematical Society 7: 1–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martin, D. 2001. Multiple Universes of Sets and Indeterminate Truth Values. Topoi 20: 5–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, W., and J. Steel 1994. Fine Structure and Iteration Trees. In Volume 3 of Lecture Notes in Logic. Berlin: Springer-Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nelson, E. 2011. Warning Signs of a Possible Collapse of Contemporary Mathematics. In Infinity: New Research Frontiers, edited by M. Heller and W.H. Woodin, 76–88. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peano, G. 1889. The Principles of Arithmetic. Presented by a New Method. In Jean van Heijenoort, 1967, A Source Book in Mathematical Logic, 1879–1931, Harvard University Press, pp. 83–97.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. 1953. Two Dogmas of Empiricism. In From a Logical Point of View, edited by W. Quine, 20–46. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1981. Theories and Things. Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shelah, S. 2003. Logical Dreams. Bulletin (New Series) of the American Mathematical Society 40: 203–228.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Steel, J. 2000. Mathematics Needs New Axioms. Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 6: 422–433.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2004. Generic Absoluteness and the Continuum Problem, downloaded from http://www. lps. uci.edu/home/conferences/Laguna-Workshops/Laguna2004.html, pp. 1–24.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steel, J. 2007. What is a Woodin Cardinal? Notices of the American Mathematical Society 54(9): 1146–1147.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wang, H. 1996. A Logical Journey: From Gödel to Philosophy. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodin, W.H. 2010a. Strong Axioms of Infinity and the Search for V. Proceedings of the International Congress of Mathematicians, Hyderabad, India, pp. 1–18.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2010b. Suitable Extender Models I. Journal of Mathematical Logic 10: 101–339.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2011a. Suitable Extender Models II: Beyond ω-Huge. Journal of Mathematical Logic 11: 115–436.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2011b. The Realm of the Infinite. In Infinity: New Research Frontiers, edited by M. Heller and W.H. Woodin, 89–118. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2011c. The Transfinite Universe. In Kurt Gödel and the Foundations of Mathematics: Horizons of Truth, edited by Matthias Baaz et al., 449–474. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2011d. The Continuum Hypothesis, the Generic Multiverse of Sets, and the Ω Conjecture. In Set Theory, Arithmetic, and Foundations of Mathematics: Theorems, Philosophies, edited by J. Kennedy and R. Kossak, 13–42. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zermelo, E. 1908. Untersuchungen über die Grundlagen der Mengenlehre I. Mathematische Annalen 65: 261–281.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

McDonnell, J. (2017). One True Mathematics. In: The Pythagorean World. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-40976-4_4

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics