Skip to main content

Individual Obligation

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Toward a Small Family Ethic

Part of the book series: SpringerBriefs in Public Health ((BRIEFSPUHEAET))

  • 1161 Accesses

Abstract

If the arguments of Chap. 2 are on track, then we likely do not have any procreation-limiting obligations grounded in the consequences of our reproductive behaviors; although creating a new human being is significant relative to our non-procreative activities, it is not absolutely significant in terms of its contribution to the harms of climate change. However, it also seems like we are sometimes obligated to refrain from actions in light of their relation to a moral problem, even if those actions don’t make a significant difference to that moral problem. But what could be the explanation for such an obligation? The goal of this chapter is to propose an answer to precisely this question. I will do this by presenting three moral principles that would seem, given the facts about our climate and the global population, to have some implication for our procreative practices. The precise content of our procreative duties, however, will be a live question. If any of the proposed principles is valid, then there seems to be good reason to believe that we ought to restrict our procreative behaviors; but does that mean that each of us is obligated to have no children? Or simply not too many (whatever that might mean)? Although I do not believe that there is an obviously correct answer to this question, I will suggest a sort of ‘limit’ to an acceptable answer.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Recall that this is how Broome actually gets to his conclusion that each of us is required to be a ‘net-zero’ emitter.

  2. 2.

    Increased atmospheric CO2 has led to oceans becoming about 30 % more acidic than they were prior to the Industrial Revolution. According to business as usual predictions, we may see a further 150 % rise in acidity by the year 2100, which would bring oceans to a pH level not seen in more than 20 million years (National Oceanic and Atmospheric Administration, n.d.)

  3. 3.

    This line of thinking was originally inspired by Fruh and Hedahl (2013); the following explication of various ways that one can ‘play a role’ in systematic harms somewhat parallels that described in (Hedahl, Fruh, & Whitlow, 2016).

  4. 4.

    Literally ‘on its face’, the language of prima facie was adopted by philosophers to denote the provisional character of duties that have not yet been weighed against the competing goods of the actual world. A prima facie duty, then, is one that I am required to follow, if it is not outweighed by some other consideration. Prima facie duties are contrasted with all-things-considered duties, which emerge at the end of the weighting and balancing process among the various, relevant goods and reason s, and which tells us what we must, in the end, do. While some prima facie duties seem to always imply an all-things-considered duty (“do not murder,” for instance), others are so all-encompassing that they regularly admit of trade-offs (“promote the good,” perhaps). What we seem to be learning at this point is that the duty not to contribute to massive harms seems to be more like the latter than the former, and so discussion of its relative justificatory burden is important.

  5. 5.

    We should be careful to recall from the introduction, that there are many resource-related reason s to be concerned with overpopulation, and I have chosen to focus on only one of them—climate change. So it could be argued that the poor residents of the world who have five, six or seven children are still contributing more to overpopulation than most Americans are, even if that overpopulation isn’t as relevant to the particular problem with climate change. However, all of the problems with overpopulation have a similar structure as the one I am dealing with here: it is not the sheer number of people that is problematic, it is the number of people given the limited availability of some resources (clean water, food, energy, etc.). And so it is actually quite difficult to argue that the high-fertility-rate poor population is contributing to the problems of overpopulation in any way, since they consume so few of the available resources. Thus, while I deal explicitly in the main text only with the case of climate change, the reader may choose to pursue another issue of resource shortage on her own, in order to see whether the populations of, say, the poorest countries in West Africa, might really be contributing to the problems of overpopulation, given these peoples’ lack of access to resources.

  6. 6.

    This is the structure of Derek Parfit’s oft-cited discussion in (Parfit, 1984). There, Parfit was concerned primarily with what he called the ‘non-identity problem’; however, in setting up the problem, he noted that it doesn’t seem we can harm a child by creating it, unless its life would be not worth living. The non-identity problem, then, is the tension between our belief that one perhaps ought to wait to have a child, if doing so would result in a healthier child, and the fact that such advice is surprisingly difficult to justify. By changing the time of conception, one changes the identity of the child. And so long as the first child would have a life worth living, then creating that child would not harm it. So it becomes surprisingly difficult to justify the intuitive claim that, say, a 15 year old girl ought to wait until she is older to get pregnant, as doing so ‘would be better for the child’.

  7. 7.

    The strongest argument to be made on the basis of this sort of consideration would look like that of the philosopher David Benatar, who holds that, for each of us, it would be better never to have been born, and so we are each obligated not to impose life on anyone else. The morally best world, then, is one in which the human species goes extinct (Benatar, 2006). Although there is much philosophically interesting to discuss in this proposal, it has convinced very few philosophers. For present purposes, we may simply note it as a ‘book-end’—the most radical position that one could take on the basis of some sort of procreative asymmetry; but I, instead, will suggest that one need not accept such a contentious view in order to be driven towards the conclusion that we each have procreation-limiting obligation s.

  8. 8.

    Note that this need not imply that the justificatory burden could not be met. Physicians who work for Doctors Without Borders presumably have a large carbon footprint as a result of their international travel; I would think that their relatively large contribution to climate change is justifiable in the way that flying from New York to Paris for a fancy lunch would not be.

References

  • Benatar, D. (2006). Better never to have been: The harm of coming into existence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Broome, J. (2012). Climate matters: Ethics in a warming world. New York: W.W. Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fruh, K., & Hedahl, M. (2013). Coping with climate change: What justice demands of surfers, mormons, and the rest of us. Ethics, Policy and Environment, 16(3), 273–296.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hedahl, M., Fruh, K., & Whitlow, L. (2016). Climate mitigation. In B. Hale & A. Light (Eds.), Routledge companion to environmental ethics. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change. (2014). Climate change 2014: Impacts, adaptation, and vulnerability. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jamieson, D. (2014). Reason in a dark time: why the struggle against climate change failed—and what it means for our future. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McMahan, J. (1981). Problems of population theory. Ethics, 92, 96–127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McMahan, J. (2009). Asymmetries in the morality of causing people to exist. In M. A. Roberts & D. T. Wasserman (Eds.), Harming future persons: Ethics, genetics and the nonidentity problem (pp. 49–68). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Murtaugh, P. A., & Schlax, M. G. (2009). Reproduction and the carbon legacies of individuals. Global Environmental Change, 19, 14–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • National Oceanic and Atmospheric Administration. (n.d.). What is ocean acidification? Retrieved January 29, 2016, from pmel.noaa.gov: http://www.pmel.noaa.gov/co2/story/What+is+Ocean+Acidification%3F.

  • Norcross, A. (2004). Puppies, pigs, and people: Eating meat and marginal cases. Nous-Supplement: Philosophical Perspectives, 18, 229–245.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. (1984). Reasons and persons. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roberts, M. A. (2011). The asymmetry: A solution. Theoria, 77(4), 333–367.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Singer, P. (2010, June 16). Last generation? A response. The New York Times. Retrieved from http://opinionator.blogs.nytimes.com/2010/06/16/last-generation-a-response/.

  • Singer, P. (2010, June 6). Should this be the last generation? The New York Times. Retrieved from http://opinionator.blogs.nytimes.com/2010/06/06/should-this-be-the-last-generation/?_r=0.

  • The World Bank. (2011–2015). CO2 emissions (metric tons per capita). Retrieved January 29, 2016, from data.worldbank.org: http://data.worldbank.org/indicator/EN.ATM.CO2E.PC/countries/1W?display=default.

  • United Nations, Department of Economic and Social Affairs, Population Division. (2015). World Fertility Patterns 2015—Data Booklet (ST/ESA/SER.A/370).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Rieder, T.N. (2016). Individual Obligation. In: Toward a Small Family Ethic. SpringerBriefs in Public Health(). Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-33871-2_3

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-33871-2_3

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-33869-9

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-33871-2

  • eBook Packages: MedicineMedicine (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics