Skip to main content

Anti-realism About Science

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Nature of Scientific Knowledge

Part of the book series: Springer Undergraduate Texts in Philosophy ((SUTP))

  • 165k Accesses

Abstract

This chapter discusses one of the major debates in philosophy of science related to scientific knowledge, the debate between realists and anti-realists. Realists maintain that our best-confirmed scientific theories are true (or at least approximately true), but anti-realists think we should only accept that our best-confirmed scientific theories are useful in some sense without committing to their truth, approximate or otherwise. Some of the major arguments on both sides of this debate are evaluated in this chapter, though special attention is paid to the so-called “miracle argument” for scientific realism. Throughout the chapter a realist stance, which allows for genuine scientific knowledge, is defended. Ultimately, the chapter concludes that while anti-realist arguments are important and worth taking seriously, they do not pose an insurmountable threat to a realist conception of science. Such a conception holds that in the case of our best-confirmed theories the truth of those theories best explains their success, which gives us justification for believing that they are true.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Giere (2006) also construes anti-realism as a species of skepticism.

  2. 2.

    The literature on scientific realism and anti-realism is vast. Our task would be made nigh impossible if we were to not only discuss realism and anti-realism in general, but also to discuss the myriad idiosyncratic formulations of these views. Additionally, there are many thought-provoking theories which fall somewhere in between realism and anti-realism such as “semirealism” (Chakravartty 1998, 2007), “scientific perspectivism” (Giere 1988, 2006), and “structural realism” (Ladyman 1998, 2011; Worrall 1989) among others. Providing a useful discussion of these theories would make this chapter unwieldy at best, and it is unnecessary for our current purpose.

  3. 3.

    Roughly, things are thought to count as observable when it is possible for humans to observe them with our unaided senses. Anything that is not observable in this sense is considered unobservable. Interestingly, there is controversy concerning whether this distinction between observable and unobservable can actually be drawn in an unproblematic way. Churchland (1985) and Musgrave (1985) argue that this distinction is problematic. See Dicken and Lipton (2006) for insightful discussion of Musgrave’s argument. This is worth pointing out because if there are problems concerning how to draw this distinction, these are problems for anti-realist views (such as that of van Fraassen 1980) which claim we can know about the observable, but not the unobservable—problems that are not shared by scientific realists (Chakravartty 2014).

  4. 4.

    Another way to understand this is that scientific realism is committed to the truth (at least for the most part) of the Real World Hypothesis defended in Chap. 11.

  5. 5.

    See Psillos (1999) for a nice discussion of what it means for a theory to be ad hoc as well as for a discussion of what is required for a theory to be mature.

  6. 6.

    Barnes (2008), Hitchcock and Sober (2004), Leplin (1997), Psillos (1999), and White (2003) all maintain that making novel predictions is important for being non-ad hoc.

  7. 7.

    The use of entailment here, and in White’s own discussion, is to simplify matters. Of course, it is plausible that a theory, the truth of which makes some data highly probable without entailing that it, predicts or accommodates that data too.

  8. 8.

    This argument is also known as the “No Miracles Argument” and the “Ultimate Argument”. For more detailed examination of the nature of this argument than we will be able to engage in here see Musgrave (1988) and Psillos (1999).

  9. 9.

    For simplicity I will often drop the qualification “approximate truth” and speak just of the truth of our best scientific theories. However, the discussion should be understood in terms of our best scientific theories being true or approximately true.

  10. 10.

    See McCain (2012) for further discussion of both of these objections.

  11. 11.

    As we noted in Chap. 10, another significant criticism of IBE is that it is inconsistent with accepted theories of probabilistic reasoning such as Bayesianism. Although the literature on this line of criticism is quite interesting, we will not explore it here. For discussion of, and responses to, this criticism of IBE see Lipton (2004), McCain & Poston (2014), McGrew (2003), Okasha (2000), Psillos (1999), and Weisberg (2009).

  12. 12.

    There are, of course, other ways of raising underdetermination problems for scientific realism. Nonetheless, the argument presented here represents the most common way of making this sort of objection. For an interesting variation on the original underdetermination argument see Stanford (2006), and for responses to Stanford see Chakravartty (2008) and Godfrey-Smith (2008).

  13. 13.

    This is actually a simplified version of Laudan and Leplin’s argument. They argue for the additional claim that observing empirical consequences of a hypothesis does not always provide evidence for the hypothesis. I do not include this part of their discussion here for two reasons. First, there are problems with the argument that Laudan and Leplin provide in support of this additional claim. Second, this additional claim is not necessary for showing that the argument in support of UD is unsound. For our purposes this is all we need to concern ourselves with, so we do not need to explore Laudan and Leplin’s additional claim. For further discussion of Laudan and Leplin’s arguments and the relation of empirical equivalence to underdetermination see Kukla (1993, 1996), Leplin (1997), and Leplin and Laudan (1993).

  14. 14.

    It should be noted that if the example presented by Laudan and Leplin actually demonstrates that two empirically equivalent theories can gain different degrees of evidential support from an observation, the example alone is sufficient to demonstrate that empirical equivalence does not entail underdetermination. This is a fact that Laudan and Leplin recognize, however, they present the rest of their argument to drive home their point. It is worth following their lead and presenting the entire argument instead of just this example because understanding the full argument helps to better illuminate the nature of the relation between empirical equivalence and underdetermination.

  15. 15.

    For discussion of the prediction versus accommodation debate see Barnes (2008), Hitchcock and Sober (2004), Harker (2006, 2008), Horwich (1982), Leplin (1997), Lipton (2004), Psillos (1999), Schlesinger (1987), and White (2003).

  16. 16.

    This is also sometimes referred to as the “Pessimistic Meta-Induction”.

  17. 17.

    See Lewis (2001) and Saatsi (2005) for similar formulations of the PI.

  18. 18.

    Another strategy for responding to the PI which has been put forward in recent years is to argue that the PI is actually a fallacious argument. Lange (2002) argues that the PI commits what he calls the “turn over fallacy”. Lewis (2001) argues that the PI commits the fallacy of false positives. Saatsi (2005) argues that both Lange and Lewis are mistaken—the PI does not commit either fallacy. Mizrahi (2013) argues that Saatsi is mistaken because the PI can be understood in three different ways, and on each understanding it is fallacious. We will not explore the merits of this strategy for responding to the PI here.

  19. 19.

    See Psillos (1999) for an excellent discussion of why many of the particular past scientific theories that Laudan refers to in pressing the PI are not actually successful.

  20. 20.

    The idea that the elements responsible for past scientific theories being empirically successful are retained in our current best theories is another point that is often claimed in response to the PI. This approach allows that past scientific theories were successful, but it casts doubt on the claim that past scientific theories were totally false. What this approach seeks to do is show that the parts of past scientific theories responsible for their empirical successes are the true parts which have been retained in our current best scientific theories. If this is correct, then the PI fails to provide a reason to doubt that empirical success is a reliable guide to the truth of a scientific theory. For this sort of approach see Kitcher (1993), Psillos (1999), and Worrall (1989).

References

  • Barnes, E. C. (2008). The paradox of predictivism. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bird, A. (2007). Nature’s metaphysics: Laws and properties. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. (1983). On the current status of the issue of scientific realism. Erkenntnis, 19, 45–90.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chakravartty, A. (1998). Semirealism. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, 29, 391–408.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chakravartty, A. (2007). A metaphysics for scientific realism: Knowing the unobservable. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chakravartty, A. (2008). What you don’t know can’t hurt you: Realism and the unconceived. Philosophical Studies, 137, 149–158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chakravartty, A. (2014). Scientific realism. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2014 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/scientific-realism/

  • Churchland, P. M. (1985). The ontological status of observables: In praise of the superempirical virtues. In P. Churchland & C. Hooker (Eds.), Images of science: Essays on realism and empiricism (pp. 35–47). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dicken, P., & Lipton, P. (2006). What can Bas believe? Musgrave and van Fraassen on observability. Analysis, 66, 226–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Doppelt, G. (2007). Reconstructing scientific realism to rebut the pessimistic meta-induction. Philosophy of Science, 74, 96–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gauch, H. G., Jr. (2012). Scientific method in brief. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. N. (1988). Explaining science: A cognitive approach. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. N. (2006). Scientific perspectivism. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2008). Recurrent transient underdetermination and the glass half full. Philosophical Studies, 137, 141–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harker, D. (2006). Accommodation and prediction: The case of the persistent head. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 57, 309–321.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harker, D. (2008). On the predilections for predictions. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 59, 429–453.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hitchcock, C., & Sober, E. (2004). Prediction versus accommodation and the risk of overfitting. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 55, 1–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoefer, C., & Rosenberg, A. (1994). Empirical equivalence, underdetermination, and systems of the world. Philosophy of Science, 61, 592–607.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horwich, P. (1982). Probability and evidence. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1993). The advancement of science: Science without legend, objectivity without illusions. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kornblith, H. (2013). Is philosophical knowledge possible? In D. E. Machuca (Ed.), Disagreement and skepticism (pp. 260–276). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kukla, A. (1993). Laudan, Leplin, empirical equivalence and underdetermination. Analysis, 53, 1–7.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kukla, A. (1996). Does every theory have empirically equivalent rivals? Erkenntnis, 44, 137–166.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, J. (1998). What is structural realism? Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, 29, 409–424.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, J. (2011). Structural realism versus standard scientific realism: The case of phlogiston and dephlogisticated air. Synthese, 180, 87–101.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lange, M. (2002). Baseball, pessimistic inductions and the turnover fallacy. Analysis, 62, 281–285.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. (1981). A confutation of convergent realism. Philosophy of Science, 48, 19–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. (1984). Science and values. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L., & Leplin, J. (1991). Empirical equivalence and underdetermination. Journal of Philosophy, 88, 449–472.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leplin, J. (1997). A novel defense of scientific realism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leplin, J., & Laudan, L. (1993). Determination underdeterred: Reply to Kukla. Analysis, 53, 8–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, P. (2001). Why the pessimistic induction is a fallacy. Synthese, 129, 371–380.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lipton, P. (2004). Inference to the best explanation (2nd ed.). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCain, K. (2012). Inference to the best explanation and the external world: A defense of the explanationist response to skepticism. PhD dissertation, University of Rochester.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCain, K., & Poston, T. (2014). Why explanatoriness is evidentially relevant. Thought, 3, 145–153.

    Google Scholar 

  • McGrew, T. (2003). Confirmation, heuristics, and explanatory reasoning. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 54, 553–567.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mizrahi, M. (2013). The pessimistic induction: A bad argument gone too far. Synthese, 190, 3209–3226.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Musgrave, A. (1985). Constructive empiricism and realism. In P. Churchland & C. Hooker (Eds.), Images of science: Essays on realism and empiricism (pp. 197–221). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Musgrave, A. (1988). The ultimate argument for scientific realism. In R. Nola (Ed.), Relativism and realism in science (pp. 229–252). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Okasha, S. (2000). Van Fraassen's critique of inference to the best explanation. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 31, 691–710.

    Google Scholar 

  • Poincaré, H. (1905/1952). Science and hypothesis. New York: Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  • Psillos, S. (1996). On van Fraassen’s critique of abductive reasoning. Philosophical Quarterly, 46, 31–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Psillos, S. (1999). Scientific realism: How science tracks truth. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1975). Philosophical papers, vol. 1: Mathematics, matter and method. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1978). Meaning and the moral sciences. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saatsi, J. T. (2005). On the pessimistic induction and two fallacies. Philosophy of Science, 72, 1088–1098.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schlesinger, G. (1987). Accommodation and prediction. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 65, 33–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smart, J. J. C. (1963). Philosophy and scientific realism. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stanford, P. K. (2006). Exceeding our grasp: Science, history, and the problem of unconceived alternatives. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B. C. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B. C. (1989). Laws and symmetry. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, J. (2009). Locating IBE in the Bayesian framework. Synthese, 167, 125–143.

    Google Scholar 

  • White, R. (2003). The epistemic advantage of prediction over accommodation. Mind, 112, 653–683.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Worrall, J. (1989). Structural realism: The best of both worlds? Dialectica, 43, 99–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

McCain, K. (2016). Anti-realism About Science. In: The Nature of Scientific Knowledge. Springer Undergraduate Texts in Philosophy. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-33405-9_14

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics