Skip to main content

Group Agents and Social Institutions: Beyond Tuomela’s Social Ontology

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Social Ontology and Collective Intentionality

Part of the book series: Studies in the Philosophy of Sociality ((SIPS,volume 8))

Abstract

In the past 30 years, collective intentionality, group agency and social institutions have established themselves as central topics within analytic philosophy. The many wide-ranging and penetrating papers and books that Raimo Tuomela has published on these topics have made a significant contribution to this development. His new book Social Ontology. Collective Intentionality and Group Agents (Oxford University Press) is a welcome addition. Tuomela formulates his ideas in a more accessible way than before, which makes the book attractive also to philosophers and social scientists that are new to his work.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Tuomela is regarded as one of the Big Four proponents of collective intentionality (Chant, Hindriks, and Preyer 2014). His contributions to the field are not restricted to his publications. Tuomela has also formed an international network of researchers that has recently constituted itself as a formal society, the International Social Ontology Society (ISOS). Participants in the network have recently established the Journal of Social Ontology.

  2. 2.

    Unqualified page references refer to Tuomela (2013). See Tuomela (2007: 39–44) for more on collective commitment.

  3. 3.

    Collective commitment comes with mutual obligations on Tuomela’s view (43). In this respect, he sides with Gilbert (1989) rather than Bratman (1999, chapter 7). See Hindriks (2013a) for a critical discussion of Gilbert’s and Bratman’s views on this matter.

  4. 4.

    In addition to collective commitment and group reasons, the we-mode encompasses the collectivity condition according to which a group goal is satisfied for a particular member only if it is satisfied for each member (40). The members of a movie club, for instance, go to the movie together as a group only if its members do indeed go to the movie.

  5. 5.

    As it presupposes intrinsic intentionality, group agents cannot have phenomenal consciousness (52, 260).

  6. 6.

    See Baker (2000, 2007) for a well-developed framework for accommodating intentional properties as part of the fabric of the world.

  7. 7.

    We-mode collective acceptance may well contribute to the functioning of some institutions. I do not see, however, why this would always be the case. Institutions sanctioned by authorities that are collectively accepted in the we-mode need not themselves be supported by such acceptance. Furthermore, some institutions involve little conflict of interests and function fine without collective commitment.

  8. 8.

    Tuomela uses the term ‘constitutive norm’ interchangeably with ‘constitutive rule’.

  9. 9.

    One might say instead that they are constitutive because the practices would not be norm-governed if it were not for the rules. Although true, this claim is trivial. ‘Constitutive’ merely indicates necessity here: necessarily, the social practice would not be governed by these rules if it were not for these rules. This claim would also be true if the relevant norms were regulative rules – as in the rules of etiquette.

  10. 10.

    Tuomela allows for institutions to involve both constitutive and regulative norms (227). It would be interesting to know more about what this means. Elsewhere I propose that constitutive rules are best seen as combinations of constitutive rules that determine the referents of institutional terms and status rules that specify their meaning in terms of the normative powers that come with the relevant statuses (Hindriks 2009). As status rules are, on my view, a kind of regulative rule, this proposal embodies a precise idea of how constitutive rules and regulative rules could be combined.

  11. 11.

    There are other ways of developing the same idea. Perhaps certain values can be realized only by means of particular rules. The idea would be that “a good” such as friendship is internal to practices governed by those rules, and accessible only to those who participate in them (see Raz 1986; Reaume 1988).

References

  • Aoki, M. (2007). Endogenizing institutions and institutional change. Journal of Institutional Economics, 3, 1–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bacharach, M. (2006). Beyond individual choice: Teams and frames in game theory. In N. Gold and R. Sugden (Ed.). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baker, L. R. (2000). Persons and bodies: A constitution view. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Baker, L. R. (2007). The metaphysics of everyday life. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. (1991). Realism, anti-foudationalism and the enthusiasm for natural kinds. Philosophical Studies, 61, 127–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bratman, M. E. (1999). Faces of intention. Selected essays on intention and agency. Cambridge: Cambridge University.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bratman, M. E. (2014). Shared agency: A planning theory of acting together. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chant, S., Hindriks, F., & Preyer, G. (2014). Beyond the big four and the big five. In S. Chant, F. Hindriks, & G. Preyer (Eds.), From individual to collective intentionality: New essays. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Copp, D. (2006). On the agency of certain collective entities: An argument from “Normative Autonomy”. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, XXX, 194–221.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (1971). Intentional systems. Journal of Philosophy, 68, 87–106.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • French, P. A. (1984). Collective and corporate responsibility. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, M. (1989). On social facts. London/New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greif, A., & Kingston, C. (2011). Institutions: Rules or equilibria? In N. Schofield & G. Caballero (Eds.), Political economy of institutions, democracy and voting (pp. 13–43). Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Grossi, D., Meyer, J.-J. C., & Dignum, F. (2006). Classificatory aspects of counts-as: An analysis in modal logic. Journal of Logic and Computation, 16, 613–643.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Guala, F., & Hindriks, F. (forthcoming). A unified social ontology. Philosophical Quarterly.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hindriks, F. (2009). Constitutive rules, language, and ontology. Erkenntnis, 71(2), 253–275.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hindriks, F. (2013a). Collective acceptance and the is-ought argument. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 16, 465–480.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hindriks, F. (2013b). The location problem in social ontology. Synthese, 190, 413–437.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • List, C., & Pettit, P. (2011). Group agency: The possibility, design, and status of corporate agents. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mäki, U. (2011). Scientific realism as a challenge to economists (and vice versa). Journal of Economic Methodology, 18, 1–12.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mäki, U. (2013). Performativity: Saving Austin from MacKenzie. In Perspectives and foundational problems in philosophy of science, V. Karakostas and D. Dieks (eds.), European Philosophy of Science Association Proceedings, 2 (443–453). Cham: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, P. (2007). Responsibility incorporated. Ethics, 117, 171–201.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1955). Two concepts of rules. Philosophical Review, 64, 3–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raz, J. (1986). Morality as freedom. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reaume, D. (1988). Individuals, groups, and rights to public goods. University of Toronto Law Review, 38(1), 1–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (1969). Speech acts: An essay in the philosophy of language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (1983). Intentionality: An essay in the philosophy of mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (1995). The construction of social reality. New York: The Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (2010). Making the social world: The structure of human civilization. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sugden, R. (2003). The logic of team reasoning. Philosophical Explorations, 6, 165–181.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tuomela, R. (2002a). The we-mode and the i-mode. In F. Schmitt (Ed.), Socializing metaphysics: The nature of social reality (pp. 93–127). Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tuomela, R. (2002b). The philosophy of social practices: A collective acceptance view. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tuomela, R. (2007). The philosophy of sociality: The shared point of view. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tuomela, R. (2013). Social ontology: Collective intentionality and group agents. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I thank Francesco Guala for helpful comments. This paper grew out of a book review (to be) published in Economics and Philosophy.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Frank Hindriks .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Hindriks, F. (2017). Group Agents and Social Institutions: Beyond Tuomela’s Social Ontology . In: Preyer, G., Peter, G. (eds) Social Ontology and Collective Intentionality. Studies in the Philosophy of Sociality, vol 8. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-33236-9_15

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics