Skip to main content

What Compromises Are

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Compromise, Peace and Public Justification
  • 351 Accesses

Abstract

In a compromise, two or more parties agree to an arrangement—the content of the compromise—but they regard the arrangement as a mere second-best. Wendt distinguishes two accounts of agreement or consent, he distinguishes moral and non-moral compromises, and he spells out what compromises need not be: compromises need not be agreed to for reasons of self-interest, they do not have to mirror the distribution of power, no process of bargaining need precede a compromise, and the parties need not have a cooperative mindset.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    This book is an exercise in systematic political philosophy. I do not engage very much in the history of ideas. For a conceptual history of compromise, see Fumurescu 2013.

  2. 2.

    Jones and O’Flynn 2013: 119–120.

  3. 3.

    The notion of a ‘second-best’ is not to be understood in the technical sense as discussed in economics (Lipsey and Lancaster 1956–1957).

  4. 4.

    Sen 1977: 326. Harsanyi ’s distinction between ethical and subjective preferences is related (1955), although ‘ethical preferences’ are much more narrowly defined than Sen ’s ‘commitments’; they are necessarily based on impartial considerations (Sen 1977: 336–337). For an extensive discussion of the distinction between conflicts of interest and conflicts of value, see Willems 2015: chs. 1–5.

  5. 5.

    Bellamy 1999: 103.

  6. 6.

    Benjamin 1990: 12, 23, May 2011: 583, Archard 2012: 404.

  7. 7.

    Lister 2007: 2, Zanetti 2011: 428.

  8. 8.

    Dobel 1990: 8.

  9. 9.

    Wertheimer 2003: 144.

  10. 10.

    Hurd 1996, Alexander 1996.

  11. 11.

    Simmons 1979: 83, Archard 1998: 4, Wertheimer 2003: 144–152.

  12. 12.

    See May 2011: 583, Lepora 2012. One can also compromise one’s interests without interacting with other persons.

  13. 13.

    See Benjamin 1990.

  14. 14.

    Wertheimer 2003: 146.

  15. 15.

    Physical strength, financial resources, and military strength are not always the most important assets (Schelling 1960: Ch. 2).

  16. 16.

    Accordingly, Benjamin distinguishes compromises as an outcome and compromising as a process (1990: 4–8). Some, though, understand compromise as ‘essentially procedural’ (Gaus 1990: 353, see Golding 1979: 7–8).

  17. 17.

    See Gaus 2011a: 393–409.

  18. 18.

    See Golding 1979: 16–19, Benditt 1979: 26–27, Benjamin 1990: 5, Bohman 1995: 268, Weinstock 2006: 244, Lister 2007: 17–18, Margalit 2010: 39–41, also Gutmann and Thompson 2012: 16–17, 101–117. Skeptical about the distinction between compromises and mere bargains are Jones and O’Flynn 2013: 120.

Bibliography

  • Alexander, Larry. 1996. The moral magic of consent II. Legal Theory 2: 165–174.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Archard, David. 1998. Sexual consent. Boulder: Westview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Archard, David. 2012. Moral compromise. Philosophy 87: 403–420.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bellamy, Richard. 1999. Liberalism and pluralism: Towards a politics of compromise. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benditt, Theodore M. 1979. Compromising interests and principles. In Compromise in ethics, law, and politics, ed. J. Pennock and J. Chapman, 26–37. New York: New York University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benjamin, Martin. 1990. Splitting the difference: Compromise and integrity in ethics and politics. Lawrence: Kansas University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bohman, James. 1995. Public reason and cultural pluralism: Political liberalism and the problem of moral conflict. Political Theory 23: 253–279.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dobel, J. Patrick. 1990. Compromise and political action: Political morality in liberal and democratic life. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fumurescu, Alin. 2013. Compromise: A political and philosophical history. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gaus, Gerald. 1990. Value and justification: The foundations of liberal theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gaus, Gerald. 2011a. The order of public reason: A theory of freedom and morality in a diverse and bounded world. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Golding, M.P. 1979. The nature of compromise. In Compromise in ethics, law, and politics, ed. J. Pennock and J. Chapman, 3–25. New York: New York University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gutmann, Amy, and Dennis Thompson. 2012. The spirit of compromise: Why governing demands it and campaigning undermines it. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harsanyi, John C. 1955. Cardinal welfare, individualistic ethics, and interpersonal comparisons of utility. Journal of Political Economy 63: 309–321.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hurd, Heidi. 1996. The moral magic of consent. Legal Theory 2: 121–146.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jones, Peter, and Ian O’Flynn. 2013. Can a compromise be fair? Politics, Philosophy & Economics 12: 115–135.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lepora, Chiara. 2012. On compromise and being compromised. Journal of Political Philosophy 20: 1–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lister, Andrew. 2007. Public reason and moral compromise. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 37: 1–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Margalit, Avishai. 2010. On compromise and rotten compromises. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • May, Simon Cabulea. 2011. Moral compromise, civic friendship, and political reconciliation. Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 14: 581–602.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schelling, Thomas C. 1960. The strategy of conflict. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen, Amartya. 1977. Rational fools: A critique of the behavioral assumptions of economic theory. Philosophy & Public Affairs 6: 317–344.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simmons, A. John. 1979. Moral principles and political obligations. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weinstock, Daniel. 2006. A neutral conception of reasonableness? Episteme 3: 234–247.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wertheimer, Alan. 2003. Consent to sexual relations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Willems, Ulrich. 2015. Wertkonflikte als Herausforderung der Demokratie. Wiesbaden: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zanetti, Véronique. 2011. Justice, peace and compromise. Analyse & Kritik 2: 423–439.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 The Editor(s) (if applicable) and The Author(s)

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Wendt, F. (2016). What Compromises Are. In: Compromise, Peace and Public Justification. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-28877-2_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics