Skip to main content

The Deontic Morality of Compromising

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Compromise, Peace and Public Justification
  • 330 Accesses

Abstract

Wendt makes some explorations in what he calls the deontic morality of compromising. He proposes and partly defends some principles regarding people’s moral duties in the process before a compromise is made, and some principles regarding people’s moral obligations after a compromise was made.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 79.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Dworkin 1986: 178–184, see also Besson 2003.

  2. 2.

    Habermas 1992/1996: 167.

  3. 3.

    Because these things are harder to realize in moral conflicts, it is a generally good advice to try to focus on ‘interests, not positions’ in bargaining (Fisher and Ury 1981).

  4. 4.

    See Jones and O’Flynn 2013: 121.

  5. 5.

    Jones and O’Flynn suggest that the notion of a fair compromise may not even apply in moral conflicts (2013: 122): the idea of fair compromise, they write, ‘applies much more readily to conflicts of interest or preference than to conflicts of principle.’

  6. 6.

    Horton 2010: 439.

  7. 7.

    Wendt 2016b. Of course, public justification also applies to other things besides modus vivendi arrangements, but as modus vivendi arrangements are constituted by some set of laws, moral rules, or institutions, they are also capable of being either publicly justifiable or not.

  8. 8.

    Scanlon has revived the debate on why and how promises ground obligations (1998: ch. 7). See also Deigh 2002, Kolodny and Wallace 2003, Southwood and Friedrich 2009.

  9. 9.

    Thomson 1990: 314.

  10. 10.

    Thomson 1990: 314–315.

  11. 11.

    Thomson 1990: 153–158, Sinnott-Armstrong 2009: 439.

  12. 12.

    Thomson 1990: 154, Sinnott-Armstrong 2009.

  13. 13.

    Gill 2012: 508.

  14. 14.

    Kukathas 2003: 252, Gray 2000: 7, Horton 2010: 444.

  15. 15.

    Horton 2010: 444. I disagree, though, that peace itself is a matter of degree (see Chap. 6).

Bibliography

  • Besson, Samantha. 2003. Four arguments against compromising justice internally. Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 23: 211–241.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deigh, John. 2002. Promises under fire. Ethics 112: 483–506.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, Ronald. 1986. Law’s empire. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher, Roger, and William L. Ury. 1981. Getting to YES: Negotiating an agreement without giving in. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gill, Michael B. 2012. The non-consequentialist moral force of promises: A response to Sinnott-Armstrong. Analysis 72: 506–513.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gray, John. 2000. Two faces of liberalism. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, Jürgen. 1992/1996. Between facts and norms: Contributions to a discourse theory of law and democracy, trans. W. Rehg. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horton, John. 2010. Realism, liberal moralism and a political theory of modus vivendi. European Journal of Political Theory 9: 431–448.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jones, Peter, and Ian O’Flynn. 2013. Can a compromise be fair? Politics, Philosophy & Economics 12: 115–135.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kolodny, Niko, and R. Jay Wallace. 2003. Promises and practices revisited. Philosophy & Public Affairs 31: 119–154.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kukathas, Chandran. 2003. The liberal archipelago: A theory of diversity and freedom. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon, Thomas. 1998. What we owe to each other. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter. 2009. How strong is this obligation? An argument for consequentialism from concomitant variation. Analysis 69: 438–442.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Southwood, Nicholas, and Daniel Friedrich. 2009. Promises beyond assurance. Philosophical Studies 144: 261–280.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thomson, Judith Jarvis. 1990. The realm of rights. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wendt, Fabian. 2016b. The moral standing of modus vivendi arrangements. Public Affairs Quarterly (forthcoming).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 The Editor(s) (if applicable) and The Author(s)

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Wendt, F. (2016). The Deontic Morality of Compromising. In: Compromise, Peace and Public Justification. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-28877-2_15

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics