Skip to main content

A More Perfect Union: Bacon’s Correspondence of Form and Policy

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Francis Bacon on Motion and Power

Abstract

A re-interpretation of Francis Bacon’s understanding of policy highlights the relationships he drew between the study of natural bodies and the formation, expansion and preservation of political bodies. Bacon’s term ‘policy’ has often been understood unproblematically as law, government or civil science. However, it should be understood in relation to the far more suspect – from both a moral and an epistemological point of view – notion of reason of state. Policy produced and managed political change. Policy offered contingent, probabilistic tools for advancing political power, but ones that were insufficiently supported by the certainty of knowledge required, in Bacon’s view, to serve as the basis for a successfully enduring polity. He hoped to design stable, perfectly mixed political bodies through grounding policy within an understanding of natural forms. However, he failed to arrive at a complete metaphysical understanding of forms, and thus did not succeed in constructing a certain, civil science. If he could not stabilize policy through natural knowledge, he could at least bring change to natural knowledge through policy. Bacon thus drew on tools for advancing actual empire in order to advance the bounds of epistemic empire. Deploying the political charlatan’s techniques for manipulating human hope, desire and our tendency to delusion, he proposed a wish-list of the most desired discoveries which might tempt humankind to extend the boundaries of epistemic empire.

This essay is an earlier version of part of a chapter, ‘Francis Bacon’s New World of Sciences’, which appears in Keller 2015. Reprinted with the permission of Cambridge University Press.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    The reason--> of state went beyond classical conceptions of cunning--> intelligence (metis) in its political and social implications. For the view that Baconian induction--> represents an attempt to transform classical metis --> (cunning intelligence), see Eamon 1994, 289. -->On cunning, Detienne and Vernant 1978. On reason -->of state more generally, Meinecke 1924; Senellart 1989; Bireley 1990; Burke 1991; Viroli 1992. Recurrent -->attempts to --> define -->the reason of -->state raised questions -->about the meaning of reason --> itself. See Melliet 1618, 358–359: ‘tous les iours nous disons, que telles, et telles choses, se font par raison d’Estat, sans bien entendre neantmoins ce qui est denoté et specifié par ce mot de Raison d’Estat: mais parce que parmi la pluspart des nations du monde, il ya Raison de nature, Raison ciuile, Raison de guerre, et Raison des gens, il sera bon d’aller examinant, quelles choses sont ces Raisons’. Scipione Chiaramonti --> listed ten meanings of ‘reason’ in --> Della ragione di stato (Chiaramonti 1635, 6–7). Erhard Weigel --> listed four types of reason other than the reason of state in De ratione status (Weigel 1667).

  2. 2.

    Sorell et al. 2010.

  3. 3.

    Caton 1988 and Martin 1993 do not discuss the reason--> of state. Wormald (1993, 186, 188) mentions --> ‘reason of -->state’ --> in passing while -->quoting --> Bacon; Faulkner (1993, 42–3, 92, 116, 155–57, 181) does discuss the reason of state in Bacon’s political -->thought. Weinberger (1985, 72, 80–82) mentions ‘ragioni di stato’. None of these authors discuss Bacon in relation to a major authority on the reason of state, Giovanni Botero -->. More generally, Poovey (1998, 86) has drawn -->attention to the problem of the reason of state or interest--> and its effects in producing institutions and a ‘new method’ to meet a new standard of ‘disinterested knowledge-->’, which formed against the background of reason of state theory. -->On interest, -->see also Stewart 1992 and Stillman 1995.

  4. 4.

    For -->instance, Peltonen 1992, 1995, 1996a, and b.

  5. 5.

    On the importance of -->transmission, see Colclough 2003.

  6. 6.

    Bacon 1623, 285: ‘Homines, cum Methodi suae Legibus res torqueant; et quaecunque in Dichotomias illas non apte cadunt, aut omittant, aut praeter Naturam inflectant; hoc efficiunt, ut quasi Nuclei et grana Scientiarum exiliant, ipsi aridas tantum et desertas Siliquas stringant’; and Bacon 1857–1874, III (Temporis partus masculus), 530: ‘Nullum mihi commercium cum hoc ignorantiae latibulo, perniciosissima literarum tinea, compendiorum patre, qui cum methodi suae et compendii vinclis res torqueat et premat, res quidem, si qua fuit, elabitur protinus et exiliit; ipse vero aridas et desertissimas nugas stringit’.

  7. 7.

    The dichotomous organization of Ramist method is readily apparent throughout Bacon’s Advancement of Learning and other philosophical works, as discussed by Richard Serjeantson --> in his paper ‘Francis Bacon and “The Inquirie Touching Humane Nature Entyer”’, delivered at the Warburg Institute, 18 June, 2011. On the Ramist roots of period --> encyclopedism, see Hotson 2011 .

  8. 8.

    See, for -->instance, Cañizares-Esguerra 2004.

  9. 9.

    Botero 1589, 1: ‘Ragione di Stato si è notitia de’ mezi, atti a fondare, -->conservare, et ampliare un Dominio’.

  10. 10.

    Note that I use ‘empire’ in the sense of imperium and as a synonym for ‘dominion’. The ‘advancement of empire’ in -->writings of the period sometimes, but not always, refers to colonial empire.

  11. 11.

    On English Tacitism, see inter --> alia Benjamin 1965, 102–110; Bradford 1983; Salmon 1989; and Smuts 1993. Tuck (1993, 116) writes, -->for -->instance, that ‘political --> debate in -->Jacobean England did not include modern arguments drawn from Botero --> or Ammirato; there was no sense of the potential world empire of the English comparable to the sense Richelieu fostered of a French universalism’. This view is beginning to be overturned. Tuck himself lists as exceptions Walter Raleigh --> and Edwin Sandys -->. See also Breen 1973, 461–462; Baldwin 2004; Fitzmaurice 2007; Malcolm 2007; Sweet 2008; and Daston 2011.

  12. 12.

    On the reason--> of state -->as ‘policy’ -->in early --> modern English, see Orsini 1946.

  13. 13.

    Martin (1993, 142) equates ‘policy’ -->with ‘laws’: ‘The crowning importance of knowledge--> of the natural world was, for Bacon, its ability to teach us these laws, “the true rules of policy”’. Wormald defines policy as ‘civil science -->’, ’a course or courses of action which this -->science dictates’, ‘the royal government’, and ‘constitutional arrangements of a state as a whole’ (p. 6), as well as ‘government’ -->and ‘law’ (Wormald 1993, 13).

  14. 14.

    According to Aristotle--> and his Renaissance revivers such as Leonardo Bruni -->, the five intellectual virtues were sapientia, scientia, prudentia, intelligentia and ars. Wisdom applied to deliberation about immutable and true things, and -->prudence --> to -->deliberation --> about mutable things, with the goal of -->taking action. See Rice 1958, 44–5; Viroli 1992, 275; Mohnhaupt 2003; and Descendre 2009, 114.

  15. 15.

    See, for -->instance, Herdesianus 1615 (De prudentia regnandi particulari seu de ratione status).

  16. 16.

    As --> recognized by Faulkner (1993, 42).

  17. 17.

    Peltonen 1992, 1995, 1996a, and b. See also Weber 2003. For another view, see Keller 2012b.

  18. 18.

    Bacon 2004, 194: ‘Primum eorum, qui propriam potentiam in Patria sua amplificatione cupiunt; quod genus vulgare est et degener. Secundum eorum, qui Patriae potentiam et Imperium inter humanum genus amplificare nituntur: Illud plus certe habet dignitatis, cupiditatis haud minus. Quod si quis humani generis ipsius potentiam et imperium in rerum Universitatem instaurare et amplificare conetur; ea proculdubio Ambitio (si modo ita vocanda sit) reliquis et sanior, est et augustior. Hominis autem imperium in Res, in solis Artibus et Scientiis ponitur’.

  19. 19.

    Botero 1589, 1: ‘Ragione -->di Stato si è notitia de’ mezi, atti a fondare, conservare, et ampliare un Dominio’.

  20. 20.

    Botero 1589, 1–2: ‘egli è vero, -->che, se bene, assolutamente parlando, ella si estende alle tre parti sudette, nondimeno pare, che più strettamente abbracci la conservatione, che l’altre; e dell’altre due più l’ampliatione, che la fondatione: e la causa si è; perché la ragione di Stato suppone il Prencipe, e lo Stato, che non suppone, anzi precede affato la fondatione, come è manifesto’.

  21. 21.

    Botero 1589, 2: ‘e l’ampliatione -->in parte: ma l’arte del fondare, e dell’ampliare è l’istessa; perché chi amplia giuditiosamente ha da fondare quel, che amplia, e da fermarvi bene il piede’.

  22. 22.

    Botero 1589, 8: ‘e sì come l’alchimia pare --> oro all’occhio, ma perde il credito al paragone, così cotali dominii hanno gran fama, e poco nervo’.

  23. 23.

    Bacon 1623, 439: ‘Cum Artes Imperii, tria Officia Politica, complectantur; Primo, ut Imperium conservetur; Secundo, ut Beatum efficiatur, et Florens; Tertio, ut amplificetur, Finesque eius longius proferantur’.

  24. 24.

    The ‘Consul Paludatus’ corresponds to the contemporary distinction between prudentia togata --> (prudence clothed in a toga) and prudentia sagata (prudence clothed in a sagum, or military cloak). Compare Lipsius 2004, 387 and à Collibus [1615] 1658, 370.

  25. 25.

    Boccalini’s Advertisements enjoyed 120 editions --> within a century. See Bosold-DasGupta 2005; Firpo 1955 and Hendrix 1995.

  26. 26.

    Bacon 1605, 24, and Bacon 1623, 173–174: ‘Etenim Magia apud Persas, pro Sapientia sublimi et Scientia consensuum rerum Universalium, accipiebatur… Nos vero eam, illo in sensu intelligimus, ut sit Scientia, quae cognitionem Formarum Abditarum ad Opera admiranda deducat, atque, quod dici solet, Activa cum Passivis coniungendo, Magnalia Naturae manifestet’.

  27. 27.

    Agrippa von Nettesheim 1550, 506: ‘Naturalem Magiam non aliud putant, quam naturalium scientiarum summam potestatem, quam idcirco summam Philosophiae naturalis apicem, ejusque absolutissimam consummationem vocant. et quae sit activa portio Philosophiae naturalis, quae naturalium virtutum adminiculo ex mutua earum et opportuna applicatione opera edit, supra omnem admirationis captum… Nam Indi et Aethiopes et Persae hac maxime praecelluere magia: qua idcirco (ut narrat Plato in Alcibiade) imbuuntur Persarum regum filii, ut ad mundanae Reipublicae imaginem, suam et ipsi Rempublicam administrare distribuereque condiscant: et Cicero in divinationum libris ait, neminem apud Persas regno potiri, qui prius Magiam non didicerit’.

  28. 28.

    Plato 1955, 122a: ‘ὧν ὁ μὲν μαγείαν τε διδάσκει τὴν Ζωροάστρου τοῦ Ὡρομάζου—ἔστι δὲ τοῦτο θεῶν θεραπεία—διδάσκει δὲ καὶ τὰ βασιλικά’.

  29. 29.

    On Pico, Jeck 2004, 283. On Bodin, Häfner 2010.

  30. 30.

    On optatives, see Keller 2012a.

  31. 31.

    Bacon 2000: ‘Etiam optatiua eorum quae adhuc non habentur, vna cum proximis suis, ad erigendam humanam industriam proponimus’.

  32. 32.

    Keller 2012a, 237. Bacon 1623, 107: ‘Impostura de imitatione fluxus et refluxus maris et amnium’.

  33. 33.

    Botero 1589 (‘Due maniere d’accrescer la gente, e le forze’), -->197: ‘La gente, e le forze s’augmentano in due modi, col propagare il suo, e col tirare a se l’altrui: si propaga il suo con l’agricoltura, con le arti, col favorire l’educatione della prole, con le Colonie: si tira a se l’altrui, con l’agregare i nemici, col rovinare le Città vicine, con la communicatione della Cittadinanza, con l’amicitia, con le Leghe, con le condotte della gente, co’ parentadi, e con gli altri simili modi’.

References

  • Agrippa von Nettesheim, Heinrich Cornelius. 1550. De occulta philosophia libri III. Lyons: Bering brothers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Asholt, Wolfgang. 1989. Nationales Programm und Satirenliterature im Umkreis der Politiques. In Nation und Literature im Europa der Frühen Neuzeit, ed. Klaus Garber, 404–428. Tübingen: Niemeyer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bacon, Francis. 1605. Twoo Bookes of the proficience and advancement of learning, divine and humane. London: Henrie Tomes.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bacon, Francis. 1623. De dignitate et augmentis scientiarum. London: John Haviland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bacon, Francis. 1625. Essayes or counsels, civill and morall. London: Hanna Barret.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bacon, Francis. 1627. New Atlantis. London: William Lee.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bacon, Francis. 1734. In Letters and remains of the Lord Chancellor Bacon, ed. Robert Stephens. London: William Bowyer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bacon, Francis. 1857–1874. Works, ed. James Spedding, Robert L. Ellis, Douglas D. Heath, 14 Vols. London: Longman [repr. Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt: Frommann, 1961–1963; Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2012].

    Google Scholar 

  • Bacon, Francis. 2000. Abcedarium nouum naturae. A new Abecedarium of nature. In The Instauratio Magna: Last writings, ed. Rees Graham. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bacon, Francis. 2004. In Instauratio magna part II: Novum organum and associated texts, ed. Graham Rees. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baldwin, Geoff. 2004. Reason of states and English parliaments, 1610–42. History of Political Thought 25: 620–641.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benjamin, Edwin B. 1965. Bacon and Tacitus. Classical Philology 60: 102–110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bireley, Robert. 1990. The counter-reformation prince: Anti-Machiavellianism or Catholic statecraft in early modern Europe. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bosold-DasGupta, Bettine. 2005. Traiano Boccalini und der Anti-Parnass. Amsterdam/New York: Rodopi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Botero, Giovanni. 1589. Della ragion di stato. Venice: Giovanni and Giovanni Paolo Giolito de’ Ferrari.

    Google Scholar 

  • Box, Ian. 1982. Bacon’s essayes: From political science to political prudence. History of Political Thought 3: 31–49.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bradford, Alan T. 1983. Stuart absolutism and the ‘utility’ of Tacitus. Huntington Library Quarterly 46: 127–155.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Breen, T.H. 1973. George Donne’s ‘Virginia Reviewed’: A 1638 plan to reform colonial society. The William and Mary Quarterly 30: 449–466.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burke, Peter. 1991. Tacitism, scepticism, and reason of state. In The Cambridge history of political thought 1450–1700, ed. J.H. Burns, 479–498. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cañizares-Esguerra, Jorge. 2004. Iberian science in the Renaissance: Ignored how much longer. Perspectives on Science 12: 86–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Caton, Hiram. 1988. The politics of progress: The origins and development of the commercial republic, 1600–1835. Gainesville: University of Florida Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chiaramonti, Scipione. 1635. Della ragione di stato. Florence: Pietro Nesti.

    Google Scholar 

  • Colclough, David. 2003. ‘Non canimus surdis, respondent omnia sylvæ’: Francis Bacon and the transmission of knowledge. In Textures of Renaissance knowledge, ed. Philippa Berry and Margaret Tudeau-Clayton, 81–97. Manchester: Manchester University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Colie, Rosalie. 1954. Cornelis Drebbel and Salomon de Caus: Two Jacobean models for Salomon’s house. The Huntington Library Quarterly 18: 245–269.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Collibus, Hippolytus à. 1658 [1615]. Princeps. Frankfurt: Corner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Daston, Lorraine. 2011. Empire of observation, 1600–1800. In Histories of scientific observation, ed. Lorraine Daston and Elizabeth Lunbeck, 81–113. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Descendre, Romain. 2009. L’état du monde: Giovanni Botero entre raison d’état et géopolitique. Geneva: Droz.

    Google Scholar 

  • Detienne, Marcel, and Jean Pierre Vernant. 1978. Cunning intelligence in Greek culture and society. Hassocks: Harvester Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eamon, William. 1994. Science and the secrets of nature: Books of secrets in medieval and early modern culture. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Faulkner, Robert K. 1993. Francis Bacon and the project of progress. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Firpo, Luigi. 1955. I ‘Ragguagli di Parnaso’ di Traiano Boccalini: Bibliografia delle edizioni italiane. Florence: Sansoni.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fitzmaurice, Andrew. 2007. The commercial ideology of colonization in Jacobean England: Robert Johnson, Giovanni Botero, and the pursuit of greatness. William and Mary Quarterly 64: 791–820.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giglioni, Guido. 2012. Philosophy according to Tacitus: Francis Bacon and the inquiry into the limits of human self-delusion. Perspectives on Science 20: 159–182.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greville, Fulke. 1633. Certaine learned and elegant workes written in his youth. London: Henry Seyle.

    Google Scholar 

  • Häfner, Ralph. 2010. Spuren des Hermetismus in Jean Bodins Colloquium heptaplomeres. In Konzepte des Hermetismus in der Literature der Frühen Neuzeit, ed. Peter-André Alt and Volkhard Wels, 133–148. Göttingen: V & R Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hale, D.G. 1971. The body politic: A political metaphor in Renaissance English literature. The Hague: Mouton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hendrix, Harald. 1995. Traiano Boccalini fra erudizione e polemica: Ricerche sulla fortuna e bibliografia critica. Florence: Olschki.

    Google Scholar 

  • Herdesianus, Cyriacus. 1615. De prudentia regnandi particulari seu de ratione status. Zerbst: Zacharias Dörffer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hotson, Howard. 2011. The Ramist roots of Comenian Pansophia. In Ramus, pedagogy and the liberal arts: Ramism in Britain and the wider world, ed. Steven John Reid and Emma Wilson, 227–252. Aldershot: Farnham.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jeck, Udo Reinhold. 2004. Platonica Orientalia. Klostermann: Frankfurt a. M.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kalff, Sabine. 2012. The body is a battlefield: Conflict and control in seventeenth-century physiology and political thought. In Blood, sweat and tears: The changing concepts of physiology from antiquity into early modern Europe, ed. Manfred Horstmanshoff, Helen King, and Claus Zittel, 171–194. Leiden: Brill.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Keller, Vera. 2012a. Accounting for invention: Guido Pancirolli’s lost and found things and the development of desiderata. Journal for the History of Ideas 73: 223–245.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keller, Vera. 2012b. Mining Tacitus: Secrets of empire, nature, and art in the reason of state. British Journal for the History of Science 45: 189–212.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keller, Vera. 2015. Knowledge and the public interest, 1575-1725. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lipsius, Justus. 2004. Politica: Six books of politics or political instruction. Trans. Jan Waszink. Assen: Royal van Gorcum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Malcolm, Noel. 2007. Reason of state, propaganda, and the thirty years’ war: An unknown translation by Thomas Hobbes. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, Julian. 1993. Francis Bacon, the state and the reform of natural philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meinecke, Friedrich. 1924. Die Idee der Staatsräson. Munich: Oldenbourg.

    Google Scholar 

  • Melliet, Laurent. 1618. Discours politiques et militaires sur Corneille Tacite. Lyon: Claude Morillon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mohnhaupt, Heinz. 2003. Prudentia-Lehren im 17. und 18. Jahrhundert. In Ins Wasser geworfen und Ozeane durchquert, Festchrift für Knut Wolfgang Nörr, ed. Mario Ascheri, Friedrich Ebel, and Martin Heckel, 617–632. Cologne: Böhlau.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mosse, George L. 1952. Puritanism and reason of state in old and new England. The William and Mary Quarterly 9: 67–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Orsini, Napoleone. 1946. ‘Policy’ or the language of Elizabethan Machiavellianism. Journal of the Warburg and Courtauld Institutes 9: 122–134.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pagden, Anthony. 1995. Heeding Heraclides: Empire and its discontents, 1619–1812. In Spain, Europe and the Atlantic world: Essays in honour of John H. Elliot, ed. Richard L. Kagan and Geoffrey Parker, 316–333. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Peltonen, Markku. 1992. Politics and science: Francis Bacon and the true greatness of states. Historical Journal 35: 279–305.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peltonen, Markku. 1995. Classical humanism and republicanism in English political thought, 1570–1640. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Peltonen, Markku. 1996a. Bacon’s political philosophy. In The Cambridge companion to Bacon, ed. Markku Peltonen, 283–310. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Peltonen, Markku. 1996b. Ciceronian humanism and Tacitean Neostoicism – replacement or transformation: The case of Francis Bacon’s moral and civil philosophy. The European Legacy 1: 220–226.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Plato. 1955. Alcibiades I. Trans. W. R. M. Lamb. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pleasant, Satyre. 1595. A pleasant Satyre or Poesie wherein is discouered the catholicon of Spayne, and the chiefe leaders of the league. Finelie Fetcht ouer, and Laide open in their colours. Newly turned out of French into English. London: Thomas Man.

    Google Scholar 

  • Poovey, Mary. 1998. A history of the modern fact: Problems of knowledge in the sciences of wealth and society. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Post, Gaines. 1964. Studies in medieval legal thought; public law and the state, 1100–1322. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rice, F. Eugene. 1958. The Renaissance idea of wisdom. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, J.H.M. 1989. Stoicism and Roman example: Seneca and Tacitus in Jacobean England. Journal of the History of Ideas 50: 199–225.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Senellart, Michel. 1989. Machiavélisme et raison d’état: XII e XVIII e siècle. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smuts, R. Malcolm. 1993. Court-centred politics and the uses of Roman historians, c. 1590–1630. In Culture and politics in early Stuart England, ed. Kevin Sharpe and Peter Lake, 21–43. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Snow, Vernon F. 1960. Francis Bacon’s advice to Fulke Greville on research techniques. The Huntington Library Quarterly 23: 369–378.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sorell, Tom, G.A.J. Rogers, and Jill Kraye (eds.). 2010. Scientia in early modern philosophy: Seventeenth-century thinkers on demonstrative knowledge from first principles. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stewart, Larry. 1992. The rise of public science: Rhetoric, technology, and natural philosophy in Newtonian Britain. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stillman, Robert. 1995. The new philosophy and universal languages in seventeenth-century England: Bacon, Hobbes, and Wilkins. Lewisburg: Bucknell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sweet, Timothy. 2008. Would Thomas More have wanted to go to Mars? Colonial promotion and bio-power. In Early modern ecostudies, ed. Ivo Kamps, Karen L. Raber, and Thomas Hallock, 269–290. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tuck, Richard. 1993. Philosophy and government, 1572–1651. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Viroli, Maurizio. 1992. From politics to reason of state: The acquisition and transformation of the language of politics, 1250–1600. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Weber, Dominique. 2003. Grandeur civique et économie dans la pensée politique de Francis Bacon. Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale 39: 323–344.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weigel, Erhard. 1667. De ratione status. Jena: Samuel Krebs.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weinberger, Jerry. 1985. Science, faith, and politics: Francis Bacon and the utopian roots of the modern age: A commentary on Bacon’s advancement of learning. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wormald, B.H.G. 1993. Francis Bacon: History, politics, and science, 1561–1626. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Vera Keller .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Keller, V. (2016). A More Perfect Union: Bacon’s Correspondence of Form and Policy. In: Giglioni, G., Lancaster, J., Corneanu, S., Jalobeanu, D. (eds) Francis Bacon on Motion and Power. International Archives of the History of Ideas Archives internationales d'histoire des idées, vol 218. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-27641-0_11

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics