Skip to main content

The Argument from Ontological Non-fundamentalism

  • Chapter
A Pluralist Theory of the Mind

Part of the book series: European Studies in Philosophy of Science ((ESPS,volume 2))

  • 617 Accesses

Abstract

The aim of this chapter is to argue for a non-reductivism that considers the scope of reductive explanations an open empirical question. Non-reductivism in this sense has to be distinguished from both reductivism and anti-reductivism. I start with the question why many contemporary philosophers consider reductivism a plausible or even an inevitable position. Given that there is hardly any inductive evidence for the truth of reductivism, I suggest that the main motivation for reductivism is the metaphysical idea of the ontological priority of the physical. This idea can be developed in a variety of ways. For example, one can specify the priority of the physical by arguing that only physical entities fundamentally exist. While this specification directly contradicts conceptual relativity, there are also more moderate (e.g. supervenience-based) specifications of the idea of ontological priority. I consider different specifications and argue that none of them are (a) compatible with conceptual relativity, (b) non-circular, and (c) strong enough to justify reductivism. I therefore conclude that conceptual relativity undermines the crucial motivation of reductivism and leads to non-reductivism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Philosophers of mind often refer to the demise of vitalism and “the explanation of life” in rather questionable ways that do not do justice to historical vitalist positions (cf. Normandin and Wolfe 2013). For the sake of the argument, however, I will leave this piece of whig history unquestioned.

  2. 2.

    This point is already a crucial motivation in Suppes’ landmark paper “on the plurality of science” (1978). For a more recent and more detailed criticism of speculations about mereological composition from a fundamental level, see Ladyman and Ross (2007).

  3. 3.

    In the spirit of a strong “naturalism of scientific practice” one could also challenge the intelligibility of metaphysical supervience because of its reliance on a dubious notion of metaphysically possible worlds. For the sake of the argument, however, I will set aside this general modal skepticism and grant metaphysicians that there is some stable notion of metaphysical supervenience.

  4. 4.

    See Chalmers (1996, 42–51). A similar notion is Terry Horgan’s “superduperveniece,” on which see Horgan (1993).

  5. 5.

    Abney et al.’s (2014) discussion of joint perceptual decision-making provides a helpful example of explanatory pluralism and of the crucial importance of non-reductive forms of integration in cognitive science. Their discussion focuses on three approaches to decision making (“behavioral/decision-making”, “linguistic/confidence”, and “physical/acoustic energy”) and the relations between them. Although the approaches cannot be reduced to each other, there are many substantive forms of theory integration. The different approaches do not only provide substantive and unique information about joint decision-making but also illuminate each other’s research results. As Abney et al. put it: “If none of these three approaches informed each other, various research opportunities crossing scales and mixing methods would be lost. For example, can people with asymmetric perceptual capabilities effectively overcome their difference by communicating about common environmental constraints (Approach 1) and what do the language properties (Approach 2) look like when they successfully coordinate?” (2014, 9) The example of joint perceptual decision-making is therefore a helpful reminder that scientific practice is often concerned with meaningful forms of integration and explanation that have little use for the opposition between reductionism and anti-reductionism.

References

  • Abney, Drew, Rick Dale, Jeff Yoshimi, Chris Kello, Kristian Tylén, and Riccardo Fusaroli. 2014. Joint Perceptual Decision-Making: A Case Study in Explanatory Pluralism. Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology 5 (330): 1–19.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brigandt, Ingo. 2013. Systems Biology and the Integration of Mechanistic Explanation and Mathematical Explanation. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 44 (4): 477–492.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, David. 1996. The Conscious Mind: In Search of a Fundamental Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, David. 2012. Constructing the World. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Craver, Carl F. 2007. Explaining the Brain. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Daly, Chris. 1997. Pluralist metaphysics. Philosophical studies 87 (2): 185–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, Daniel C. 1988. Quining Qualia. In Consciousness in Modern Science, eds. Anthony J. Marcel and Eduard Bisiach, 42–77. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eronen, Markus I. 2011. Reduction in Philosophy of Mind: A Pluralistic Account. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gervais, Raoul and Looren De Jong, Huib 2013. The Status of Functional Explanation in Psychology: Reduction and Mechanistic Explanation. Theory and Psychology 23 (2): 145–163.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horgan, Terence. 1993. From Supervenience to Superdupervenience: Meeting the Demands of a Material World. Mind 102 (408): 555–86.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hüttemann, Andreas. 2003. What’s Wrong with Microphysicalism? New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, James, and Don Ross. 2007. Every Thing Must Go: Metaphysics Naturalized. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • MacBride, Fraser. 2005. Lewis’s Animadversions on the Truthmaker Principle. In Truthmakers: The Contemporary Debate, eds. Helen Beebee and Julian Dodd, 117–40. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • McLaughlin, Brian. 1995. Varieties of Supervenience. In Supervenience: New Essays, eds. Elias E Savellos and Ümit D Yalçin, 16–59. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Normandin, Sebastien, and Charles T. Wolfe. 2013. Vitalism and the scientific image in post-enlightenment life science, 1800-2010. Berlin: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Piccinini, Gualtiero, and Carl Craver. 2011. Integrating Psychology and Neuroscience: Functional Analyses as Mechanism Sketches. Synthese 183 (3): 283–311.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, Jonathan. 2010. Monism: The Priority of the Whole. Philosophical Review 119 (1): 31–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schlick, Moritz. 1918/1974. General Theory of Knowledge. Vienna: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlick, Moritz. Letter to Ernst Cassirer‖, 1927. Inv. No. 94. Schlick-Paper

    Google Scholar 

  • Smart, John JC. 1959. Sensations and Brain Processes. The Philosophical Review 68 (2): 141–56.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stoljar, Daniel. 2010. Physicalism. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suppes, Patrick. 1978. The Plurality of Science. PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, 3–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, Jessica. 2010. What Is Hume’s Dictum, and Why Believe It? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 80 (3): 595–637.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, James. 2008. Mental Causation and Neural Mechanisms. In Being Reduced, eds. Jakob Hohwy and Jesper Kallestrup, 52–74. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Ludwig, D. (2015). The Argument from Ontological Non-fundamentalism. In: A Pluralist Theory of the Mind. European Studies in Philosophy of Science, vol 2. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-22738-2_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics