Advertisement

Natures of Curved Lines in the Early Modern Period and the Emergence of the Transcendental

  • Bruce J. PetrieEmail author
Conference paper
  • 492 Downloads
Part of the Proceedings of the Canadian Society for History and Philosophy of Mathematics/La Société Canadienne d’Histoire et de Philosophie des Mathématiques book series (PCSHPM)

Abstract

The transition from the geometric study to the algebraic study of curved lines changed how early modern mathematicians understood the origins of these mathematical objects. To know a mathematical object was to know its nature. To know its nature was to know its origin. The emergence of the transcendental classification was a consequence of a shift in how mathematicians understood the natures of mathematical objects because they were classified according to their natures. This nature was useful to determine which objects were appropriate for geometrical study, especially when applied to curves. The development of calculus provided the tools necessary for algebraic analysis to uncouple the study of curves and geometry, greatly increasing the number of curves which could be made known. The geometrical motivation for classifying curves was rendered obsolete and was replaced by focusing on functional relationships between variables. The nature of mathematical objects inherited the nature of the algebraic expression used to represent them.

Keywords

Mathematical Object Curve Line Classification Rule Geometric Construction Conic Section 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Notes

Acknowledgements

The author would like to thank the members of the CSHPM, members of his dissertation committee, and the reviewers for their encouraging comments and helpful criticisms.

References

  1. Aristotle. (2000). The Internet Classics Archive. Physics by Aristotle, written 350 B.C.E.: Translated by R.P. Hardie and R.K. Gaye. http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/physics.html.
  2. Bos, H. J. M. (1981). On the Representation of Curves in Descartes’ Géométrie. Archive for History of Exact Sciences, 24, 295–338.zbMATHMathSciNetCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Bos, H. J. M. (2001). Redefining Geometrical Exactness: Descartes’ Transformation of the Early Modern Concept of Construction. New York: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Descartes, R. (1925). The Geometry of Ren Descartes: Translated from the French and Latin with a Facsimile of the First Edition, 1637. Chicago: The Open Court Publishing Company. Translated by David Eugene Smith and Marcia L. Latham.Google Scholar
  5. Euler, L. (1990). Introduction to the Analysis of the Infinite. New York: Springer. Translated by John D. Blanton.zbMATHCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Fried, M. N., & Unguru, S. (2001). Apollonius of Perga’s Conica: Text, Context, Subtext. Boston: Brill.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2015

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Institute for the History and Philosophy of Science and TechnologyUniversity of TorontoTorontoCanada

Personalised recommendations