Skip to main content

Deontology and Natural Hazards

  • Chapter
Risk Analysis of Natural Hazards

Part of the book series: Risk, Governance and Society ((RISKGOSO,volume 19))

Abstract

In this chapter, I explore some fundamental moral questions about how we should evaluate disaster policy. I offer a challenge to the dominant approach, namely cost-benefit analysis, arguing that we need to give weight to some crucial moral distinctions that this approach ignores, such as the difference between doing and allowing harm. In place of cost-benefit analysis, I defend an alternative “deontological” approach, which incorporates these distinctions. But I also show that more work is needed to fully develop a deontological theory of disaster policy. There are fruitful new avenues in this area for both policy analysts and moral theorists.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    For further discussion of consequentialism see Sinnott-Armstrong (2011).

  2. 2.

    See, for instance, Adler and Posner (2006) for further explanation of this approach.

  3. 3.

    As described in, for instance, Adler and Posner (2006, Chap. 3).

  4. 4.

    Of course, there is huge debate about whether this is a good explanation or whether we should take seriously our common-sense judgments. It is well outside the scope of this paper to offer a full defense of the distinction: I’m just trying to explain the basic motivation.

  5. 5.

    They also often incorporate other related distinctions, such as the intending/foreseeing distinction, but in this paper I will focus on just the doing/allowing distinction, which is less controversial.

  6. 6.

    The language of “constraints” comes from Nozick (1974)’s discussion.

  7. 7.

    Zamir and Medina (2010) ask whether the relevant function involves a multiplier, K, rather than, say, a fixed factor F that one adds to the harm. I chose the first function simply because I think it fits people’s judgments about the various examples better. When we consider cases that involve inflicting greater and greater harm, the benefits required to morally outweigh the harm seem to scale up proportionately.

  8. 8.

    Someone might say here that there is some arbitrariness in the distinction between performing two separate actions together, Actions 1 and Action 2, versus performing the single Action 3: for instance, maybe when I shoot at B quickly after shooting at A I can just as easily be said to have performed Action 3. But this is no help to the absolutist. It just suggests the unhappy implication that (according to absolutism) the same behavior can be permissible under one plausible description, yet impermissible under another equally plausible description.

  9. 9.

    For an interesting way of denying the Two Rights principle, see Aboodi et al. (2008), but see also Huemer’s reply (Huemer 2010, pp. 345–347).

  10. 10.

    See also Alexander and Moore (2012) for further problems with absolutism.

  11. 11.

    For a similar perspective, see Zamir and Medina (2010).

  12. 12.

    The resulting theory will of course still retain some of the basic structure of CBA/consequentialism, requiring us to quantify and consider the costs and benefits of our actions. But I think this is to be welcomed: it shows that we can take all of these factors into account even while weighing them in a manner that respects deontological distinctions. Deontologists can take advantage of the attractively quantitative approach to policy analysis of CBA/consequentialism without accepting all of its dictates.

  13. 13.

    For discussion of these examples see Zamir and Medina (2010) and Hosein (2014).

  14. 14.

    See Murphy and Gardoni (2011) for a more extensive argument that familiar duties from common-sense morality and the law have an important bearing on dealing with natural hazard risks.

  15. 15.

    We shouldn’t draw this contrast too sharply, though, because even apparently clear cases of “non-natural” risk also involve some interaction with the natural world. For instance, in describing the House example, I said that using certain materials would create a risk of a brick eventually becoming dislodged and striking a pedestrian. It’s natural to think of this as a situation where the (potential) risk is due to factors solely internal to the structure and thus as a situation where by building the house I simply create an entirely “non-natural” threat. But really the source of the risk includes not just facts about the internal structure of the house but the way that it is likely to interact with ordinary wind, rain, subsistence, etc. So there relevant difference is probably one of degree.

  16. 16.

    Farber et al. (2009) give many examples of legal disputes surrounding disaster hazards where multiple institutions and actors are involved and the difficulties of assigning legal responsibility in these cases.

  17. 17.

    See Cranor (2007) and Hansson (2013, Chap. 7.2–7.3) for further discussion of the role of individuals in exposing themselves to risk.

  18. 18.

    Chapter 15, in this book.

  19. 19.

    Though, as I have noted, there are important relevant discussions in Cranor (2007), Murphy and Gardoni (2011), and Hansson (2013).

  20. 20.

    For instance, Posner and Vermeule (2006, p. 40) complain that threshold deontology has an “arbitrary flavor” and Alexander and Moore (2012) raise the same objection. In the context of risk evaluation, see Hansson (2013, Chap. 2.3) for a similar concern that the deontologist doesn’t have a full theory of how to make trade-offs.

  21. 21.

    It might be said that Scanlon (1998)’s contractualism is an important alternative, but I’m skeptical about the theory as a whole and it would also still require a lot of use of intuition to make trade-offs, of the kind that I am about to describe. See Hosein (2013) for elaboration of both of these issues.

  22. 22.

    Though, admittedly, there is some important literature that aims to question the particular kinds of judgment relied on by deontologist. See, for instance, Greene (2007), but see also, for an important rejoinder Berker (2009). I can’t pursue those issues fully here.

  23. 23.

    For discussion of these views see Parfit (1997). See also Adler (2011) for a defense of incorporating distributive concerns into the cost-benefit framework.

  24. 24.

    See Goodin (1995) for a defense of the claim that Bentham was particularly focused on political morality.

  25. 25.

    Bentham doesn’t explicitly speak of thresholds, but his remarks about different balances people will strike between harming, aiding and so on suggest the same issue.

References

  • Aboodi R, Borer A, Enoch D (2008) Deontology, individualism, and uncertainty: a reply to Jackson and Smith. J Philos 55:259–272

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Adler MD (2011) Well-being and distribution: beyond cost-benefit analysis. Oxford University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Adler MD, Posner EA (2006) New foundations of cost-benefit analysis. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexander L (2000) Deontology at the threshold. San Diego Law Rev 37(4):893–912

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexander L, Moore M (2012) Deontological ethics (Winter 2012 Edition). In: Zalta EN (ed) The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2012/entries/ethics-deontological/

  • Bentham J (1823) An introduction to the principles of morals and legislation. W. Pickering, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Berker S (2009) The normative insignificance of neuroscience. Philos Public Aff 37:293–329

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen GA (2009) Rescuing justice and equality. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Cranor C (2007) Towards a non-consequentialist approach to risk. In: Lewens T (ed) Risk: philosophical perspectives. Routledge, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Farber D, Chen J, Verchick R, Sun L (2009) Disaster law and policy. Kluwer, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Fried BH (2012) The Limits of a nonconsequentialist approach to torts. Legal Theory 18:231–262

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodin RE (1995) Utilitarianism as a public philosophy. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Greene JD (2007) The secret joke of Kant’s soul. In: Sinnott-Armstrong W (ed) Moral psychology: the neuroscience of morality: emotion, disease, and development, vol 3. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Hansson SO (2013) The ethics of risk: ethical analysis in an uncertain world. Palgrave MacMillan, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hosein A (2013) Contractualism, politics, and morality. Acta Anal 28(4):495–508

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hosein A (2014) Doing, allowing, and the state. Law Philos 33(2):235–264

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huemer M (2010) Lexical priority and the problem of risk. Pac Philos Q 91(3):332–351

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson F, Smith M (2006) Absolutist moral theories and uncertainty. J Philos 103:267–283

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Murphy C, Gardoni P (2011) Evaluating the source of the risks associated with natural events. Res Publica 17(2):125–140

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nozick R (1974) Anarchy, state, and utopia. Basic Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Parfit D (1997) Equality and priority. Ratio 10(3):202–221

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Posner EA, Vermeule A (2006) Terror in the balance. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon TM (1998) What we owe to each other. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Sinnott-Armstrong W (2011) Consequentialism (Spring 2014 Edition). In: Zalta EN (ed) The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/consequentialism/

  • Zamir E, Medina B (2010) Law, economics, and morality. Oxford University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Adam Hosein .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Hosein, A. (2016). Deontology and Natural Hazards. In: Gardoni, P., Murphy, C., Rowell, A. (eds) Risk Analysis of Natural Hazards. Risk, Governance and Society, vol 19. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-22126-7_9

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics