Skip to main content

Exploring the Workings of the Psyche: Metatheoretical and Methodological Foundations

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Psychology as the Science of Human Being

Part of the book series: Annals of Theoretical Psychology ((AOTP,volume 13))

Abstract

Introspection is considered a key method for exploring the workings of the psyche because psychical phenomena are accessible only by the individual him or herself. But this epistemological concept, despite its importance, remained unclear and contentious. Its scientificity is often questioned, but still introspective findings from psychophysics are widely accepted as the ultimate proof of the quantifiability of psychical phenomena. Not everything going on in individuals’ minds is considered introspection, but clear criteria that qualify explorations as introspective are still missing. This research applies the Transdisciplinary Philosophy-of-Science Paradigm for Research on Individuals (TPS-Paradigm) to metatheoretically define the peculiarities of psychical phenomena of which various kinds are differentiated and to derive therefrom basic methodological principles and criteria applicable to any investigation. Building on these foundations, the TPS-Paradigm introduces the concepts of introquestion versus extroquestion and reveals that introspection cannot be clearly differentiated from extrospection and that psychophysical experiments and some first-person perspective methods are not introspective as often assumed. The chapter explores the challenges that arise from the fact that psychical phenomena can be explored only indirectly through individuals’ behavioural and semiotic externalisations and scrutinises what, when, where and how to externalise in introquestive explorations. The basic principles and criteria elaborated also allow for determining which kind of psychical phenomenon can be explored by using which kind of method for establishing an appropriate phenomenon–methodology match.

Author biography

Jana Uher is a Senior Research Fellow at The London School of Economics and Political Science. She received her PhD from Free University Berlin in 2009, where she headed the group Comparative Differential and Personality Psychology from 2010–2013, funded by the Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft (DFG). In 2013, Jana Uher was awarded a Marie Curie Fellowship by the European Commission. Her research is transdisciplinary, concentrating on philosophy-of-science issues of psychological and behavioral research on individuals from culture- and species-comprehensive perspectives. She employs a broad portfolio of methods in studies with human children and adults with different sociocultural backgrounds and more than ten different nonhuman species, in particular primates. Jana Uher has been working at the Max Planck Institute for Evolutionary Anthropology in Leipzig (2003–2005) and has also been a visiting scholar at the Institute of Cognitive Sciences and Technologies, National Research Council of Italy (ISTC-CNR) in Rome (2011–2013).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    The TPS-Paradigm uses the term psychical rather than psychological because “events, processes and structures that are properly called psychical do not become psychological until they have been operated upon in some way by the science of psychology” (Adams and Zener in Lewin 1935, p. vii).

  2. 2.

    The presuppositions that the TPS-Paradigm makes about the three metatheoretical properties and the distinctions between various kinds of phenomena need not be consensually shared by all scientists. Scientists who do not agree or who agree only partially with these presuppositions must develop metatheoretical and methodological concepts other than the ones that are explored in this research, thus precluding direct comparisons (for details, see Uher 2015a, d).

  3. 3.

    The term “non-physical” is put in quotation marks because it denotes properties that are not simply contrasted against the physical but are complementary instead (see below; Uher 2015a).

  4. 4.

    In the TPS-Paradigm, the term phenomenon denotes anything that is or can be (technically) made perceptible and/or that can be conceived by humans. This differs from various historical thought traditions in which phenomena are conceived of as mere sensory perceptions and are differentiated from non-sensual concepts (sometimes called noumena; e.g. Kant 1781; for details, see Uher 2015d).

  5. 5.

    For a differentiation to the concepts of internalism versus externalism, see the Section “Indirect Exploration Through Individuals’ Behavioural and Semiotic Externalisations”.

  6. 6.

    Given these non-spatial properties, the entirety of psychical phenomena cannot be conceived of as a material physical entity that could be directly perceived as is possible for individuals’ bodies; thus, notions of “the psyche” in the TPS-Paradigm cannot and do not imply reification as a concrete entity.

  7. 7.

    Given that complex organismal systems function as organised wholes, the so-called principle of emergence denotes that their properties cannot be deduced from the knowledge of the constituting elements and their interrelations. When such systems are assembled from their elements, new characteristics of the whole emerge, and these could not have been predicted from knowledge of their constituents and the interrelations between them. The whole has different properties, structures and functionings (e.g. Rothschuh 1963; Uher 2015a, d; Wundt 1863).

  8. 8.

    Sensations are physiological processes, operating at the border from the physical to the psychical into which they become processed as perceptions. Sensory phenomena enable conversions of information from external physical events into internal psychical events. Importantly, the patterns according to which sensations are converted into percepts are not fixed and sensations are not the only ways in which perceptions are generated (Gibson 1967; for details, see Uher 2015d).

  9. 9.

    Wundt (1874) already emphasised that the possibilities for quantification are restricted to simple psychical phenomena accessible by psychophysical experimentation and that such possibilities are not given for higher and complex psychical phenomena for the exploration of which he developed his comprehensive research programme of cultural–historical psychology (German: Völkerpsychologie).

  10. 10.

    Previously also called the one-sided gap of the mindenvironment connection (Uher 2013).

  11. 11.

    The term mediation refers to the Latin mediare, to be in the middle.

  12. 12.

    The TPS-Paradigm conceives of functions as temporal interrelations that regularly occur between particular kinds of phenomena, events or properties—thus, as established effects (derived from the Latin effectus for “worked out, brought about, accomplished”). Functions thus defined imply neither purpose nor intention because teleological properties presuppose that possible prospective outcomes are simulated and evaluated on the basis of a posteriori analyses of experiences made in the past, which is possible only for psychical phenomena (Uher 2015d). Moreover, functions denote not only causal connections of various kind (Kausal-Zusammenhänge) but also compositional connections (Gefüge-Zusammenhänge) in which the interacting elements co-occur in coordinated ways and match and cooperate with one another such that the entirety of their joint interactions results in complexes and functions of higher organisation (Rothschuh 1963; Uher 2015a, c, e).

  13. 13.

    The corresponding German terms are bewusstseinspflichtig and bewusstseinsfähig (Hacker 1986).

  14. 14.

    A situation is defined in the TPS-Paradigm as the particular constellation of the internal and external events that are present in a given moment and that the individual can therefore directly perceive, consciously or not (Uher 2015a).

  15. 15.

    Experiencings also occur during some episodes of sleep (e.g. dream experiencing).

  16. 16.

    The German term Aktualgenese, coined by Gestaltpsychologists for perceptual processes, is derived from the Latin actualis for in action, operative. This German term refers more explicitly to the time-bound properties of the phenomena studied than the corresponding English term microgenesis, which refers to the smallest, moment-by-moment transformative occurrences of continuous developmental processes (Diriwächter and Valsiner 2008).

  17. 17.

    Of course, what individuals can extroquestively access and what cameras can technically capture is necessarily not exactly the same. Audiovisual cameras may be less or even more sensitive to audiovisual events, but are generally insensitive to physical events of other kind (e.g. of smells, temperature, humidity, air pressure) that individuals can extroquestively access.

  18. 18.

    Original wording “dem Ausdruck der Gedanken eine Grenze ziehen”—literally translated “to draw a limit to the expression of thoughts” (Wittgenstein 1922, Preface).

References

  • Adams, D. K. & Zener, K. E. (1935). Translators’ preface. In K. Lewin (1935). A dynamic theory of personality. Selected papers. New York and London: McGraw Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bohr, N. (1937). Causality and complementarity. Philosophy and Science, 4, 289–298.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boring, E. G. (1953). A history of introspection. Psychological Bulletin, 50, 169–189.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Bower, G. H. (1967). A multicomponent theory of the memory trace. The psychology of learning and motivation. Advances in Research and Theory, 1, 229–325.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brentano, F. C. (1874). Psychologie vom empirischen Standpunkt. Leipzig: Duncker & Humblot.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brunswik, E. (1955). Representative design and probabilistic theory in a functional psychology. Psychological Review, 62, 193–217.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Bühler, K. (1907). Tatsachen und Probleme zu einer Psychologie der Denkvorgänge I. Über Gedanken. Archiv für die gesamte Psychologie, 9, 297–365.

    Google Scholar 

  • Butler, J. (2013). Rethinking introspection. A pluralist approach to the first-person perspective. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cherney, I. D., Seiwert, C. S., Dickey, T. M., & Flichtbeil, J. D. (2006). Children’s drawings: A mirror to their minds. Educational Psychology, 26, 127–142.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Collingwood, R. G. (1940). An essay on metaphysics. Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diriwächter, R., & Valsiner, J. (Eds.). (2008). Striving for the whole: Creating theoretical syntheses. Somerset, NJ: Transaction Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eich, E., & Metcalfe, J. (1989). Mood dependent memory for internal versus external events. Journal of Experimental Psychology Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 15, 433–455.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fahrenberg, J. (2013). Zur Kategorienlehre der Psychologie Komplementaritätsprinzip. Perspektiven und Perspektiven-Wechsel. Lengerich: Pabst Science Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fechner, G. Th. (1888). Ueber die psychischen Maßprincipien und das Webersche Gesetz. Philosophische Studien, 4, 161–230.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher, R. P., & Geiselman, R. E. (1992). Memory enhancing techniques for investigative interviewing: The cognitive interview. Springfield, IL: Charles Thomas.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flick, U. (2008). Managing quality in qualitative research. London, UK: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freud, S. (1915). The unconscious. Standard Edition, 14, 159–214.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibson, J. J. (1967). New reasons for realism. Synthese, 17, 162–172.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gillespie, A., & Zittoun, T. (2010). Studying the movement of thought. In A. Toomela & J. Valsiner (Eds.), Methodological thinking in psychology: 60 years gone astray (pp. 69–88). Charlotte, NC: Information Age Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacker, W. (1886). Arbeitspsychologie. Psychische Regulation von Arbeitstätigkeiten. Stuttgart und Bern: Huber.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (1990). The intrinsic quality of experience. In J. Tomberlin (Ed.), Philosophical Perspectives (Vol. 4, pp. 31–52). Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hintzman, D. L., & Block, R. A. (1971). Repetition and memory: Evidence for a multiple trace hypothesis. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 88, 297–306.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hirschberger, J. (1980a). Geschichte der Philosophie. Band I Altertum und Mittelalter. Zweitausendeins: Frankfurt am Main.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hirschberger, J. (1980b). Geschichte der Philosophie Band II Neuzeit und Gegenwart. Zweitausendeins: Frankfurt am Main.

    Google Scholar 

  • James, W. (1890). The principles of psychology. Cambridge, MA: Harvard.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1781/1998). Kritik der reinen Vernunft (Hrsg. J. Timmermann). Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1786/1968). Metaphysische Anfangsgründe der Naturwissenschaft (Hrsg. B. Erdmann, P. Menzer, & A. Höfler). Preussische Akademie der Wissenschaften, Textausgabe Band IV (pp. 465–565). Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1798/2000). Anthropologie in pragmatischer Hinsicht (Hrsg. R. Brandt). Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, G. A. (1955). The psychology of personal constructs (Vols. 1 and 2). New York, NY: Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koffka, K. (1935). Principles of Gestalt psychology. New York: Harcourt, Brace, & World.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. S. (1962). The structure of scientific revolutions (1st ed.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lahlou, S. (2011). How can we capture the subject’s perspective?: An evidence-based approach for the social scientist. Social Science Information, 50, 607–655.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lahlou, S., Le Bellu, S. & Boesen-Mariani, S. (2015). Subjective evidence-based ethnography: Method and applications. Integrative Psychological and Behavioral Science, 49, 216–238.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lau, J. & Deutsch, M. (2014). Externalism about mental content. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2014 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (Ed.), http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2014/entries/content-externalism; retrieved Feb, 15, 2015.

  • Le Poidevin, R. (2011). The experience and perception of time. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2011 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (Ed.), http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2011/entries/time-experience/; retrieved Apr, 15, 2014.

  • Locke, J., (1689). Essay concerning human understanding. Book I. The Project Gutenberg EBook #10615. http://www.gutenberg.org; retrieved Sept, 08, 2013.

  • McAdams, D. (2001). The psychology of life stories. Review of General Psychology, 5, 100–122.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mead, G. H. (1934). Mind, self, and society. Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Memon, A., & Bull, R. (1991). The cognitive interview: Its origins, empirical support, evaluation and practical implications. Journal of Community and Applied Psychology, 1, 1–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. (1993). White queen psychology and other essays for Alice. Bradford: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. (1974). What is it like to be a bat? The Philosophical Review, 83, 435–450.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C. S. (1902). Collected papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. 1–6, C. Hartshorne & P. Weiss (eds.), vols. 7–8, A. W. Burks (ed.), (1931–1935/1958–1966). Cambridge, MA: Belknap Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pink, S. (2015). Going forward through the world: Thinking theoretically about first person perspective digital ethnography. Integrative Psychological and Behavioral Science, 49, 239–252.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenbaum, P. J., & Valsiner, J. (2011). The un-making of a method: From rating scales to the study of psychological processes. Theory and Psychology, 21, 47–65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roth, W.-M. (2012). First person methods: Towards an empirical phenomenology of experience. Rotterdam, The Netherlands: Sense Publishers.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rothschuh, K. E. (1963). Theorie des Organsimus. Bios—Psyche—Pathos (2. erw. Aufl.). München: Urban & Schwarzenberg.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rowlands, M. (2003). Externalism: Putting mind and world back together again. Acumen: McGill-Queen’s University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schacter, D. L., & Addis, D. R. (2007). Constructive memory: Ghosts of past and future. Nature, 445, 27.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Schwitzgebel, E. (2014). Introspection. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2014 Edition), E. N. Zalta (Ed.), http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2014/entries/introspection; retrieved Jan, 31, 2015.

  • Semon, R. W. (1909). Die mnemischen Empfindungen in ihren Beziehungen zu den Originalempfindungen. Leipzig: W. Engelmann. English translation: Semon, R. W. (1923). Mnemonic psychology. London, UK: George Allen & Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skinner, B. F. (1957). Verbal behavior. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Toomela, A. (2011). Travel into a fairy land: A critique of modern qualitative and mixed methods psychologies. Integrative Psychological and Behavioral Science, 45, 21–47.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Toomela, A., & Valsiner, J. (Eds.). (2010). Methodological thinking in psychology: 60 years gone astray? Charlotte, NC: Information Age Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tulving, E. (1983). Elements of episodic memory. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tulving, E., & Thomson, D. M. (1973). Encoding specificity and retrieval processes in episodic memory. Psychological Review, 80, 352–373.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Uher, J. (under review a). Principles of measurement and quantification in the physical sciences, life sciences, social sciences and in psychology.

    Google Scholar 

  • Uher, J. (under review b). Objectivity in psychology: Standardised assessments standardise only the data format but not the data generation.

    Google Scholar 

  • Uher. J. (under review c). What’s wrong with ratings?

    Google Scholar 

  • Uher, J. (2011). Individual behavioral phenotypes: An integrative meta-theoretical framework. Why ‘behavioral syndromes’ are not analogues of ‘personality’. Developmental Psychobiology, 53, 521–548.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Uher, J. (2013). Personality psychology: Lexical approaches, assessment methods, and trait concepts reveal only half of the story—Why it is time for a paradigm shift. Integrative Psychological and Behavioral Science, 47, 1–55.

    Article  PubMed Central  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Uher, J. (2014). Fundamental challenges of contemporary “personality” research. Physics of Life Reviews, 11, 695–696.

    Google Scholar 

  • Uher, J. (2015a). Conceiving “personality”: Psychologists’ challenges and basic fundamentals of the Transdisciplinary Philosophy-of-Science Paradigm for Research on Individuals. Integrative Psychological and Behavioral Science, 49, xx–xx. doi:10.1007/s12124-014-9283-1

    Google Scholar 

  • Uher, J. (2015b). Developing “personality” taxonomies: Metatheoretical and methodological rationales underlying selection approaches, methods of data generation and reduction principles. Integrative Psychological and Behavioral Science, 49, xx–xx. doi:10.1007/s12124-014-9280-4

    Google Scholar 

  • Uher, J. (2015c). Interpreting “personality” taxonomies: Why previous models cannot capture individual-specific experiencing, behaviour, functioning and development. Major taxonomic tasks still lay ahead. Integrative Psychological and Behavioral Science, 49, xx–xx. doi:10.1007/s12124-014-9281-3

    Google Scholar 

  • Uher, J. (2015d). Agency enabled by the Psyche: Explorations using the Transdisciplinary Philosophy-of-Science Paradigm for Research on Individuals. Annals of Theoretical Psychology, 12, 177–228.

    Google Scholar 

  • Uher, J. (2015e). Comparing individuals within and across situations, groups and species: Metatheoretical and methodological foundations demonstrated in primate behaviour. In D. Emmans & A. Laihinen (Eds.), Comparative Neuropsychology and Brain Imaging (Vol. 2), Series Neuropsychology: An Interdisciplinary Approach (pp. 223–284) Berlin: Lit Verlag. doi:10.13140/RG.2.1.3848.8169

  • Valsiner, J. (1987). Culture and the development of children’s actions: A cultural–historical theory of developmental psychology. New York, NY: John Wiley & Sons.

    Google Scholar 

  • Valsiner, J. (1998). The guided mind. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Valsiner, J. (2012). A guided science: History of psychology in the mirror of its making. New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vygotsky, L. S. (1934/1962). Thought and language. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wagoner, B. (2009). The experimental methodology of constructive microgenesis. In J. Valsiner, P. Molenaar, N. Chaudhary, & M. Lyra (Eds.), Handbook of dynamic process methodology in the social and developmental sciences (pp. 99–121). New York: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Weber, M. (1946). From Max Weber: Essays in sociology. (H. H. Gerth & C. W. Mills, Eds.). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber, M. (1949). The methodology of the social sciences (E.A. Shils and H.A. Finch, Trans (Eds.)). New York, NY: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1922). Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. Logisch-philosophische Abhandlung. London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wundt, W. (1863). Vorlesungen über die Menschen- und Thierseele. Hamburg: Voss.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wundt, W. (1874). Grundzüge der physiologischen Psychologie (Vol. 3). Leipzig: Wilhelm Engelmann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wundt, W. (1894). Über psychische Kausalität und das Prinzip des psycho-physischen Parallelismus. Philosophische Studien, 10, 1–124.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wundt, W. (1896). Grundriss der Psychologie. Stuttgart: Körner. Online at https://archive.org/; Accessed July, 20, 2014.

  • Wundt, W. (1920). Logik. Eine Untersuchung der Prinzipien der Erkenntnis und der Methoden Wissenschaftlicher Forschung. Band 2. Logik der exakten Wissenschaften (4. Aufl.). Stuttgart: Enke.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

The author acknowledges funding from the German Research Foundation (DFG; UH249/1-1). This chapter was previously entitled “Exploring individuals and the workings of their minds: Methodological principles derived from the Transdisciplinary Philosophy-of-Science Paradigm for Research on Individuals”.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jana Uher .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Uher, J. (2016). Exploring the Workings of the Psyche: Metatheoretical and Methodological Foundations. In: Valsiner, J., Marsico, G., Chaudhary, N., Sato, T., Dazzani, V. (eds) Psychology as the Science of Human Being. Annals of Theoretical Psychology, vol 13. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-21094-0_18

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics